Web
and Book design,
Copyright, Kellscraft Studio 1999-2017 (Return to Web Text-ures) |
(HOME)
|
I THE MYSTERY OF JUSTICE I SPEAK for those who do not believe in the existence of a unique, all-powerful, infallible Judge, for ever intent on our thoughts, our feelings and actions, maintaining justice in this world, and completing it in the next. And if there be no Judge, what justice is there? None other than that which men have made for themselves by their laws and tribunals, as also in the social relations that no definite judgment governs? Is there nothing above this human justice, whose sanction is rarely other than the opinion, the confidence or mistrust, the approval or disapproval, of our fellows? Is this capable of explaining or accounting for all that seems so inexplicable to us in the morality of the Universe, that we at times feel almost compelled to believe an intelligent Judge must exist? When we deceive or overcome our neighbour, have we deceived or overcome all the forces of justice? Are all things definitely settled then, and may we go boldly on; or is there a graver, deeper justice, one less visible perhaps, but less subject to error; one that is more universal, and mightier? That such a justice exists we all of us
know, for we
all have felt its irresistible power. We are well aware that it covers
the
whole of our life, and that at its centre there reigns an intelligence
which
never deceives itself, and which none can deceive. But where shall we
place it,
now that we have torn it down from the skies? Where does it weigh good and evil,
happiness and
disaster? Whence does it issue to deal out reward and punishment? These
are
questions we do not often ask ourselves, but they have their
importance. The
nature of justice, and all our morality, depend on the answer; and it
cannot be
fruitless, therefore, to inquire how that great idea of mystic and
sovereign
justice, which has undergone more than one transformation since history
began,
is being received to-day in the heart and mind of man. And is this
mystery not
the loftiest, the most passionately interesting, of all that remain to
us; does
it not intertwine with most of the others? Do its vacillations not stir
us to
the very depths of our soul? The great bulk of mankind perhaps know
nothing of
these vacillations and changes, but for the evolution of thought it
suffices
that the eyes of the few should see; and when the clear consciousness
of these
has become aware of the transformation, its influence will gradually
attain the
general morality of men. [2] In these pages we shall naturally have
much to say of
social justice; in other words, of the justice that we mutually extend
to each
other through life; but we shall leave on one side legal or positive
justice,
which is merely the organisation of one side of social justice. We
shall occupy
ourselves above all with that vague but inevitable justice, intangible,
and yet
so effective, which accompanies and sets its seal upon every action of
our
life; which approves or disapproves, rewards or punishes. Does this
come from
without? Does an inflexible, undeceivable moral principle exist,
independent of
man, in the universe and in things? Is there, in a word, a justice that
might
be called mystic? Or does it issue wholly from man; is it inward even
though it
act from without; and is the only justice therefore psychologic? These
two
terms, mystic and psychologic justice, comprehend, more or less, all
the
different forms of justice, superior to the social, that would appear
to exist
to-day. [3] It is scarcely conceivable that any one
who has
forsaken the easy, but artificially illumined, paths of positive
religion, can
still believe in the existence of a physical justice arising from moral
causes,
whether its manifestations assume the form of heredity or disease, of
geologic,
atmospheric, or other phenomena. However eager his desire for illusion
or
mystery, this is a truth he is bound to recognise from the moment he
begins
earnestly and sincerely to study his own personal experience, or to
observe the
external ills which, in this world of ours, fall indiscriminately on
good and
wicked alike. Neither the earth nor the sky, neither nature nor matter,
neither
air nor any force known to man (save only those that are in him),
betrays the
slightest regard for justice, or the remotest connection with our
morality,
thoughts, or intentions. Between the external world and our actions
there exist
only the simple and essentially non-moral relations of cause and
effect. If I
am guilty of a certain excess or imprudence, I incur a certain danger,
and have
to pay a corresponding debt to nature. And as this imprudence or excess
will
generally have had an immoral cause — or a cause that we call immoral
because
we have been compelled to regulate our life according to the
requirements of
our health and tranquillity — we cannot refrain from establishing a
connection
between this immoral cause and the danger to which we have been
exposed, or the
debt we have had to pay; and we are led once more to believe in the
justice of
the universe, the prejudice which, of all those that we cling to, has
its root
deepest in our heart. And in our eagerness to restore this confidence,
we are
content deliberately to ignore the fact that the result would have been
exactly
the same had the cause of our excess or imprudence been — to use the
terms of
our infantine vocabulary — heroic or innocent. If on an intensely cold
day I
throw myself into the water to save a fellow-creature from drowning, or
if,
seeking to drown him, I chance to fall in, the consequences of the
chill will
be absolutely the same, and nothing on this earth or beneath the sky —
save
only myself, or man if he be able — will enhance my suffering because I
have
committed a crime, or relieve my pain because my action was virtuous. [4] Let us consider another form of physical
justice, —
heredity. There again we find the same indifference to moral causes.
And truly
it were a strange justice indeed that would throw upon the son, and
even the
remote descendant, the burden of a fault committed by his father or his
ancestor. But human morality would raise no objection; man would not
protest.
To him it would seem natural, magnificent, even fascinating. It would
indefinitely prolong his individuality, his consciousness and
existence, and
from this point of view would accord with a number of indisputable
facts which
prove that we are not wholly self-contained, but connect, in more than
one
subtle, mysterious fashion, with all that surrounds us in life, with
all that
precedes us, or follows. And yet, true as this may be in certain
cases, it is
not true as regards the justice of physical heredity, which is
absolutely
indifferent to the moral causes of the deed whose consequences the
descendants
have to bear. There is physical relation between the act of the father,
whereby
he has undermined his health, and the consequent suffering of the son;
but the
son’s suffering will be the same whatever the intentions or motives of
the
father, be these heroic or shameful. And, further, the area of what we
call the
justice of physical heredity would appear to be very restricted. A
father may
have been guilty of a hundred abominable crimes; he may have been a
murderer, a
traitor, a persecutor of the innocent, or a despoiler of the wretched,
without
these crimes leaving the slightest trace upon the organism of his
children. It
is enough that he should have been careful to do nothing that might
injure his
health. [5] So much for the justice of nature, as
shown in
physical heredity. Moral heredity would appear to be governed by
similar
principles, but, as it deals with modifications of the mind and
character
infinitely more complex and elusive, its manifestations are less
striking, and
its results less certain. Pathology is the only region which permits of
its
definite observation and study; and there we observe it to be merely
the
spiritual form of physical heredity, which is its essential principle;
moral
heredity being only a sequel, and revealing in its elementary stage the
same
indifference to real justice, and the same blindness. Whatever the
moral cause
of the ancestor’s drunkenness or debauch, the same punishment may be
meted out
in mind and body to the descendants of the drunkard and the debauchee.
Intellectual blemish will almost always accompany material blemish. The
soul
will be attacked simultaneously with the body: and it matters but
little
whether the victim be imbecile, mad, epileptic, possessed of criminal
instincts, or only vaguely threatened with slight mental derangement:
the most
frightful moral penalty that a supreme justice could invent has
followed
actions which, as a rule, cause less harm and are less perverse than
hundreds
of other offences that nature never dreams of punishing. And this
penalty,
moreover is inflicted blindly, not the slightest heed being paid to the
motives
underlying the actions, motives that may have been excusable perhaps,
or
indifferent, or possibly even admirable. It would be absurd, however, to imagine
that
drunkenness and debauchery are the only agents in moral heredity. There
are a
thousand others, all more or less unknown. Certain moral qualities
appear to be
transmitted as readily as though they were physical. In one race, for
instance,
we shall almost constantly discover certain virtues which have probably
been
acquired. But who shall say how much is due to heredity and how much to
environment and example? The problem becomes so complicated, the facts
so
contradictory, that it is impossible, amidst the mass of innumerable
causes, to
follow the track of one particular cause to the end. Let it suffice to
say
that, in the only clear, striking definitive cases where an intentional
justice
could have revealed itself in physical or moral heredity, no trace of
justice
is found. And if we do not find it in these, we are surely far less
likely to
find it in others. [6] We may affirm, therefore, that not above
us, around
us, or beneath us; neither in this life nor in our other life which is
that of
our children, is the least trace to be found of an intentional justice.
But in
the course of adapting ourselves to the laws of life, we have naturally
been
led to credit with our own moral ideas those principles of causality
that we
encounter most frequently; and we have in this fashion created a very
plausible
semblance of effective justice, which rewards or punishes most of our
actions
in the degree that they approach, or deviate from, certain laws that
are essential
for the preservations of the race. It is evident that if I sow my field
I shall
have an infinitely better prospect of reaping a harvest the following
summer
than my neighbour, who has neglected to sow his, preferring a life of
dissipation and idleness. In this case, therefore, work obtains its
admirable
and certain reward; and as work is essential for the preservation of
our
existence, we have declared it to be the moral act of all acts, the
first of
all our duties. Such instances might be indefinitely multiplied. If I
bring up
my children well, if I am good and just to those round about me, if I
am
honest, active, prudent, wise, and sincere in all my dealings, I shall
have a
better chance of meeting with filial piety, with respect and affection,
a better
chance of knowing moments of happiness, than the man whose actions and
conduct
have been the very reverse of mine. Let us not, however, lose sight of
the fact
that my neighbour, who is, let us say, a most diligent and thrifty man,
might
be prevented by the most admirable of reasons, such as an illness
caught while
nursing his wife or his friend, from sowing his ground at the proper
time, and
that he also would reap no harvest. Mutatis mutandis, similar results
would
follow in the other instances I have mentioned. The cases, however, are
exceptional where a worthy or respectable reason will hinder the
accomplishment
of a duty; and we shall find, as a rule, that sufficient harmony exists
between
cause and effect, between the exaction of the necessary law and the
result of
the complying effort, to enable our casuistry to keep alive within us
the idea
of the justice of things.
This idea, however, deeply ingrained
though it be in
the hearts and minds of the least credulous and least mystic of men,
can surely
not be beneficial. It reduces our morality to the level of the insect,
which,
perched on a falling rock, imagines that the rock has been set in
motion on its
own special behalf. Can there be certain errors and falsehoods that we
do well
to keep alive? There may have been some in the past which, for a
moment, were
helpful; but, this moment over, men found themselves once again face to
face
with the truth, and the sacrifice had only been delayed. Why wait till
the
illusion or falsehood which appeared to do good begins to do actual
harm, or,
if it do no harm, at least retards the perfect understanding that
should obtain
between the deeply felt reality and our manner of interpreting and
accepting
it? What were the divine right of kings, the infallibility of the
Church, the
belief in rewards beyond the grave, but illusions whose sacrifice
reason
deferred too long? Nor was anything gained by this dilatoriness beyond
a few
sterile hopes, a little deceptive peace, a few consolations that at
times were
disastrous. But many days had been lost; and we cannot afford to lose
many
days, we who at last are seeking the truth, and find in its search an
all-sufficient reason for existence. Nor does anything retard us more
than the
illusion which, though torn from its roots, we still permit to linger
among us;
for this will display the most extraordinary activity, and be
constantly
changing its form. But what does it matter, some will ask,
whether man
do the thing that is just because he thinks God is watching — because
he believes
in a kind of justice that pervades the universe — or for the simple
reason that
to his conscience this thing seems just? It matters above all. We have
there
three different men. The first, whom God is watching, will do much that
is not
just, for every God whom man has hitherto worshipped has decreed many
unjust
things. And the second will not always act in the same way as the
third, who
is, indeed, the true man to whom the moralist will turn, for he will
survive
both the others; and to foretell how man will conduct himself in truth,
which
is his natural element, is more interesting to the moralist than to
watch his
behaviour when enmeshed in falsehood. [8] It may seem idle to those who do not
believe in the
existence of a sovereign Judge to discuss so seriously this
inadmissible idea
of the justice of things. And inadmissible it does, indeed, seem when
presented
thus, in its true colours, pinned to the wall as it were. This,
however, is not
our way of regarding it in every-day life. When we observe how disaster
follows
crime, how ruin at last overtakes ill-gotten prosperity — when we
witness the
miserable end of the debauchee, the short-lived triumph of iniquity, it
is our
constant habit to confuse the physical effect with the moral cause; and
however
little we may believe in the existence of a Judge, we nearly all of us
end by a
more or less complete submission to a strange, vague faith in the
justice of
things. And though our reason, our calm observation, prove to us that
this
justice cannot exist, it is enough that an event should take place
which
touches us somewhat more nearly, or that there should be two or three
curious
coincidences, for conviction to fade in our heart, if not in our mind.
Notwithstanding all our reason and all our experience, the merest
trifle
recalls to life within us the ancestor who was convinced that the stars
shone
in their eternal places for no other purpose than to predict or approve
a wound
he was to inflict on his enemy upon the field of battle, a word he
should speak
in the assembly of the chiefs, or an intrigue he should bring to a
successful
issue in the women’s quarters. We of to-day are no less inclined to
divinise
our feelings to serve our interests; the only difference being that,
the gods
having no longer a name, our methods have become less sincere and less
precise.
When the Greeks, powerless before Troy, felt the need of supernatural
signal
and support, they went to Philoctetes, deprived him of Hercules’ bow
and
arrows, and abandoned him ill, naked, and defenceless on a desert
island. This
was the mysterious Justice, loftier than that of man: this was the
command of
the gods. And similarly do we, when some iniquity seems expedient to
us, cry
loudly that we do it for the sake of posterity, of humanity, of the
fatherland.
On the other hand, should a great misfortune befall us we protest that
there is
no justice, that there are no gods; but let the misfortune befall our
enemy,
and the universe is at once re-peopled with invisible Judges. If,
however, some
unexpected, disproportionate stroke of good fortune come to us, we are
quickly
convinced that we must possess merits so carefully hidden as to have
escaped
our own observation; and we are happier in their discovery than at the
windfall
they have procured us. [9] “One has to pay for all things,” we say.
Yes, in the
depth of our heart, in all that pertains to man, justice exacts payment
in the
coin of our personal happiness or sorrow. And without, in the universe
that
enfolds us, there is also a reckoning; but here it is a different
paymaster who
measures out happiness or sorrow. Other laws obtain, there are other
motives,
other methods. It is no longer the justice of the conscience that
presides, but
the logic of nature, which cares nothing for our morality. Within us is
a
spirit that weighs only intentions, without us a power that only
balances
deeds. We try to persuade ourselves that these two work hand in hand.
But in
reality, though the spirit will often glance towards the power, this
last is as
completely ignorant of the other’s existence as is the man weighing
coals in
Northern Europe of the existence of his fellow weighing diamonds in
South
Africa. We are constantly intruding our sense of justice into this
non-moral
logic; and herein lies the source of most of our errors. [10] And further, what right have we to
complain of the
indifference of the universe, what right to declare it incomprehensible
and
monstrous? Why this surprise at an injustice in which we ourselves have
taken
so active a part? It is true that no trace of justice can be found in
disease,
accident, or most of the hazards of external life, which fall
indiscriminately
on the good and the wicked, the hero and the traitor, the poisoner and
the
sister of charity. But we are far too eager to include under the title
“Justice
of the Universe" many a flagrant act that is exclusively human, and
infinitely more common and more destructive than disease, the
hurricane, or
fire. I do not allude to war; it might be urged that we attribute this
rather
to the will of the peoples or kings than to nature. But poverty, for
instance,
which we still rank with irremediable ills, such as shipwreck or
plague;
poverty, with all its crushing sorrows and transmitted degeneration —
how often
may this be ascribed to the injustice of the elements, and how often to
the
injustice of our social condition, which is the crowning injustice of
men? Need
we, at the sight of unmerited wretchedness, look to the skies for a
reason, as
though a flash of lightning had caused it? Need we seek an
impenetrable,
unfathomable Judge? Is this region not our own; are we not here in the
best
explored, best known portion of our dominion; and is it not we who
organise
misery, we who spread it abroad, as arbitrarily, from the moral point
of view,
as fire and disease scatter destruction or suffering? Is it reasonable
that we
should wonder at the sea’s indifference to the soul-state of its
victims, when
we who have a soul, the pre-eminent organ of justice, pay no heed
whatever to
the innocence of the countless thousands whom we ourselves sacrifice,
who are
our own wretched victims? We choose to regard as beyond our control, as
a force
of fatality, a force that rests entirely within our own hands. But does
this
excuse us? Truly we are strange lovers of an ideal justice, we are
strange
judges! A judicial error sends a thrill of horror from one end of the
world to
another; but the error which condemns three-fourths of mankind to
misery, an
error as purely human as that of any tribunal, is attributed by us to
some
inaccessible, implacable Power. If the child of some honest man we know
be born
blind, imbecile, or deformed, we will seek everywhere, even in the
darkness of
a religion we have ceased to practise, for some God whose intention to
question; but if the child be born poor — a calamity as a rule no less
capable
than the gravest infirmity of degrading a creature’s destiny — we do
not dream
of interrogating the God who is wherever we are, since he is made of
our own
desires. Before we demand an ideal Judge we shall do well to purify our
ideas,
for whatever blemish there is in these will surely be found in the
Judge.
Before we complain of Nature’s indifference, or ask at her hand an
equity she
does not possess, let us attack the iniquity that dwells in the homes
of men;
and when this has been swept away we shall find that the part we assign
to the
injustice of fate will be less by fully two-thirds. And the benefit to
mankind
would be far more considerable than if it lay in our power to guide the
storm
or govern the heat and the cold, to direct the course of disease or the
avalanche, or contrive that the sea should display an intelligent
regard to our
virtues and secret intentions. For, indeed, the poor far exceed in
number those
who fall victims to shipwreck or material accident, just as far more
disease is
due to material wretchedness than to the caprice of our organism, or
the
hostility of the elements. [11] And for all that, we love justice. We
live, it is
true, in the midst of a great injustice; but we have only recently
acquired
this knowledge, and we still grope for a remedy. Injustice dates such a
long
way back; the idea of God, of destiny, of nature’s mysterious decrees,
had been
so closely and intimately associated with it, and is still so deeply
entangled
with most of the unjust forces of the universe, that it was but
yesterday that
we commenced the endeavour to isolate such elements contained within it
as are
purely human. And if we succeed; if we can distinguish them, and
separate them
for all time from those upon which we are powerless, justice will gain
more
than by all that man has discovered hitherto in his search for justice.
For
indeed in this social injustice of ours it is not the human part that
is
capable of checking our passion for equity; it is the part that a great
number
of men still attribute to a god, to a kind of fatality, or to imaginary
laws of
nature. [12] This last, inactive part shrinks every
day. Nor is
this because the mystery of justice is about to disappear. A mystery
rarely
disappears — as a rule, it only shifts its ground. But it is often most
important and most desirable that we should bring about this change of
abode.
It may be said that two or three such changes almost stand for the
whole
progress of human thought: the dislodgment of two or three mysteries
from a
place where they did harm, and their transference to a place where they
become
inoffensive and capable of doing good. Sometimes even, there is no need
for the
mystery to change its place; we have only to identify it under another
name.
What was once called “the gods,” we now term “life.” And if life be as
inexplicable as were the gods, we are at least the gainers to the
extent that
no one has the right to speak or do wrong in its name. The aim of human
thought
can scarcely be to destroy mystery, or lessen it, for that seems
impossible. We
may be sure that the same quantity of mystery will ever enwrap the
world, since
it is the quality of the world, as of mystery, to be infinite. But
honest human
thought will seek above all to determine what are the veritable
irreducible
mysteries. It will endeavour to strip them of all that does not belong
to them,
that is not truly theirs, of the additions made by our errors, our
fears, and
our falsehoods. And as the artificial mysteries vanish, so will the
ocean of
veritable mystery stretch further and further: the mystery of life, its
aim and
its origin; the mystery of thought; the mystery that has been called
“the
primitive accident" or the “perhaps unknowable essence of reality.” [13] Where had men conceived the mystery of
justice to
lodge? It pervaded the world. At one moment it was supposed to rest in
the
hands of the gods, at another it engulfed and mastered’ the gods
themselves. It
had been imagined everywhere except in man. It had dwelt in the sky, it
had
lurked behind rocks, it had governed the air and the sea, it had
peopled an
inaccessible universe. Then at last we peered into its imaginary
retreats, we
pressed close and examined; its throne of clouds tottered, it faded
away; but,
at the very moment we believed it had ceased to be, behold it
reappeared, and
raised its head once more in the very depths of our heart; and yet
another
mystery had sought refuge in man; and embodied itself in him. For it is
in
ourselves that the mysteries we seek to destroy almost invariably find
their
last shelter and their most fitting abode, the home which they had
forsaken, in
the wildness of youth, to voyage through space; and it is in ourselves
that we
must learn to meet and to question them. And truly it is no less
wonderful, no
less inexplicable, that man should have in his heart an unchanging
instinct of
justice, than it was wonderful and inexplicable that the gods should be
just,
or the forces of the universe. It is as difficult to account for the
essence of
our memory, our will, or intelligence, as it was to account for the
memory,
will, or intelligence, of the invisible powers or laws of nature; and
if, in
order to enhance our curiosity, we have need of the unknown or
unknowable; if,
in order to maintain our ardour, we require mystery or the infinite, we
shall
not lose a single tributary of the unknown and unknowable by at last
restoring
the great river to its primitive bed; nor shall we have closed a single
road
that leads to the infinite, or lessened by the minutest fraction the
most
contested of veritable mysteries. Whatever we take from the skies we
find again
in the heart of man. But, mystery for mystery, let us prefer the one
that is
certain to the one that is doubtful, the one that is near to the one
that is
far, the one that is in us and of us to the harmful one from without.
Mystery
for mystery, let us no longer parley with the messengers, but with the
sovereign who sent them; no longer question those feeble ones who
silently
vanish at our first inquiry, but rather look into our heart, where are
both
question and answer — the answer which it has forgotten, but some day,
perhaps,
shall remember. [14] Then we shall be able to solve more than
one
disconcerting problem as to the distribution, often very equitable, of
reward
and punishment among men. And by this we do not mean only the inward,
moral
reward and punishment, but also the reward and punishment that are
visible and
wholly material. There was some measure of reason in the belief, held
by
mankind from its very origin, that justice penetrates, animates as it
were,
every object of this world in which we live. This belief has not been
explained
away by the fact that our great moral laws have been forcibly adapted
to the
great laws of life and matter. There is more beyond. We cannot refer
all
things, in all circumstances, to a simple relation of cause and effect
between
crime and punishment. There is often a moral element also; and, though
events
have not placed it there, though it is we alone who have created it, it
is not
the less powerful and real. Of a physical justice, properly so-called,
we deny
the existence; but besides the wholly inward psychologic justice, to
which we
shall soon refer, there is also a psychologic justice which is in
constant
communication with the physical world; and it is this justice that we
attribute
to we know not what invisible and universal principle. And while it is
wrong to
credit nature with moral intentions, and to allow our actions to be
governed by
fear of punishment or hope of reward that she may reserve for us, this
does not
imply that, even materially, there is no reward for good, or punishment
for
evil. Such reward and punishment undoubtedly exist, but they issue not
from
whence we imagine; and in believing that they come from an inaccessible
spot,
that they master us, judge us, and consequently dispense us from
judging
ourselves, we commit the most dangerous of errors; for none has a
greater
influence upon our manner of defending ourselves against misfortune, or
of
setting forth to attempt the legitimate conquest of happiness. [15] Such justice as we actually discover in
nature does
not issue from her, but from ourselves, who have unconsciously placed
it there
by becoming one with events, by animating them, and adapting them to
our uses.
Accident, disease, lightning, which strike to right or to left, without
apparent reason or warning, are not the only elements in our life.
There are
other, and far more frequent, cases when we have direct influence on
the things
and the persons around us, and invest these with our own personality;
cases
where the forces of nature become instruments for our thoughts, which,
when
unjust, will make improper use of them, thereby calling forth
retaliation and
inviting punishment and disaster. But in nature there is no moral
reaction; for
this emanates from our own thoughts, or the thoughts of other men. It
is not in
things, but in us, that the justice of things resides. It is our moral
condition that modifies our conduct towards the external world; and if
we find
this antagonistic, it is because we are at war with ourselves, at war
with the
essential laws of our mind and our heart. The attitude of nature
towards us is
uninfluenced by the justice or injustice of our intentions; and yet
these will
almost invariably govern our attitude towards nature. Here once more,
as in the
case of social justice, we ascribe to the universe, to an
unintelligible,
eternal, fatal principle, a part that we play ourselves; and when we
say that
justice, Heaven, nature, or events are rising in revolt against us to
punish or
revenge, it is in reality man who is using events to punish man; it is
human
nature that rises in revolt, and human justice that avenges. [16] In a former essay I referred to Napoleon’s
three
crowning acts of injustice: the three celebrated crimes that were so
fatally
unjust to his own fortune. The first was the murder of the Duc
d’Enghien,
condemned by order, without trial or proof, and executed in the
trenches of
Vincennes, — an assassination that sowed insatiable hatred and
vengeance in the
path of the guilty dictator. Then the detestable intrigues whereby he
lured the
too trustful, easy-going Bourbons to Bayonne, that he might rob them of
their
hereditary crown; and the horrible war that ensued, a war that cost the
lives
of three hundred thousand men, swallowed up all the morality and energy
of the
empire, most of its prestige, almost all its convictions, almost all
the
devotion it inspired, and engulfed its prosperous destiny. And finally
the
frightful, unpardonable Russian campaign, wherein his fortune came at
last to
utter shipwreck amid the ice of the Berezina and the snowbound Polish
steppes. “These prodigious catastrophes,” I said,
“had
numberless causes; but when we have slowly traced our way through all
the more
or less unforeseen circumstances, have marked the gradual change in
Napoleon’s
character, and noted the acts of imprudence, folly, and violence which
this
genius committed; when we have seen how deliberately he brought
disaster to his
smiling fortune, may we not almost believe that what we behold,
standing erect
at the very fountain-head of calamity, is no other than the silent
shadow of
misunderstood human justice? Human justice, possessing nothing
supernatural,
nothing very mysterious; built up of many thousand very real little
incidents,
many thousand falsehoods, many thousand little offences, of which each
one gave
rise to a corresponding act of retaliation — human justice, and not a
power
that suddenly, at some tragic moment, leaps forth like Minerva of old,
fully
armed, from the formidable, despotic brow of destiny. In all this there
is only
one thing of mystery, and that is the eternal presence of human
justice; but we
are aware that the nature of man is very mysterious. Let us in the
meanwhile
ponder this mystery. It is the most certain of all, it is the
profoundest, it
is the most helpful, it is the only one that will never paralyse our
energy for
good. And though this patient, vigilant shadow be not as clearly
defined in
every life as it was in Napoleon’s, though justice be not always as
active or
as undeniable, we shall none the less do wisely to study a case like
this
whenever opportunity offers. It will at least give rise to doubt within
us, it
will stimulate inquiry; and these things are worth far more than the
idle,
short-sighted affirmation or denial that we so often permit ourselves;
for in
all questions of this kind our endeavour should not be to prove, but
rather to
arouse attention, to create a certain grave, courageous respect for all
that
yet remains unexplained in the actions of men, in their subjection to
what
appear to be general laws, and in the results that ensue.” [17] Let us now try to discover in what way
this great
mystery of justice does truly and inevitably work itself out within us.
The
heart of him who has committed an unjust act becomes the scene of
ineffaceable
drama, the paramount drama of human nature, which becomes the more
dangerous,
and deadlier, in the degree of the man’s greatness and knowledge. A Napoleon will say to himself, at such
troubled
moments, that the morality of a great life cannot be as simple as that
of an
ordinary one, and that an active, powerful will has rights which the
feeble and
inert will cannot claim. He will hold that he may the more legitimately
sweep
aside certain conscientious scruples, inasmuch as it is not ignorance
or
weakness that causes him to disregard these, but the fact that he views
them
from a standpoint higher than that of most men; and further, that, his
aim
being great and glorious, this passing deliberate callousness of his is
therefore truly a victory won by his strength and his intellect, since
there
can be no danger in doing wrong when it is done by one who does it
knowingly,
and has his very good reason. All this, however, does not for a moment
delude
that which lies deepest within us. An act of injustice must always
shake the
confidence a man had in himself and his destiny; at a given moment, and
that
generally of the gravest, he has ceased to rely upon himself alone; and
this
will not be forgotten, nor will he ever again be wholly himself. He has
confused and probably corrupted his fortune by the introduction of
strange
powers. He has lost the exact sense of his personality and of the force
that is
in him. He can no longer clearly distinguish between what is his own
and comes
from himself, and what he is constantly borrowing from the pernicious
collaborators whom his weakness has summoned. He has ceased to be the
general
who has none but disciplined soldiers in the army of his thoughts; he
becomes
the usurping chief around whom are only accomplices. He has forsworn
the
dignity of the man who will have none of the glory at which his heart
can only
smile as sadly as an ardent, unhappy lover would smile at a faithless
mistress. He who is truly strong will examine with
eager care
the praise and advantages that his actions have won for him; and will
silently
reject whatever oversteps a certain line that he has drawn in his
consciousness. And the stronger he is, the more nearly will this line
approach
the one that has already been drawn by the secret truth that lies at
the bottom
of all things. An act of injustice is almost always a confession of
weakness;
and very few such confessions are needed to reveal to the enemy the
most
vulnerable spot of the soul. He who commits an unjust deed that he may
gain
some measure of glory, or preserve the little glory he has, does but
admit that
what he desires or what he possesses is beyond his deserving, and that
the part
he has sought to play exceeds his powers of loyal fulfilment. And if,
notwithstanding
all, he persists in his endeavour, his life will be soon beset by
falsehoods,
errors, and phantoms. And at last, after a few acts of weakness,
of
treachery, of culpable self-indulgence, the survey of our past life can
bring
discouragement only, whereas we have great need that our past should
inspire
and sustain us. For therein alone do we truly know what we are; it is
only our
past that can come to us, in our moments of doubt, and say: “Since you
were
able to do that thing, it shall lie in your power to do this thing
also. When
that danger confronted you, when that terrible grief laid you
prostrate, you
had faith in yourself and you conquered. The conditions to-day are the
same; do
you but preserve your faith in yourself, and your star will be
constant.” But
what reply shall we make if our past can only whisper: “Your success
has been
solely due to injustice and falsehood, wherefore it behoves you once
more to
deceive and to lie.” No man cares to let his eyes rest on his acts of
disloyalty, weakness, or treachery; and all the events of bygone days
which we
cannot contemplate calmly and peacefully, with satisfaction and
confidence,
trouble and restrict the horizon which the days that are not yet are
forming
far away. It is only a prolonged survey of the past that can give to
the eye
the strength that it needs in order to sound the future. [18] No, it was not the inherent justice of
things that
punished Napoleon for his three great acts of injustice, or that will
punish us
for our own, in a less startling, but not less painful, fashion. Nor
was it an
unyielding, incorruptible, irresistible justice, “attaining the very
vault of
heaven.” We are punished because our entire moral being, our mind no
less than
our character, is incapable of living and acting except in justice.
Leaving
that, we leave our natural element; we are carried, as it were, into a
planet
of which we know nothing, where the ground slips from under our feet
and all
things disconcert us; for while the humblest intellect feels itself at
home in
justice, and can readily foretell the consequences of every just act,
the most
profound and penetrating mind loses its way hopelessly in the injustice
itself
has created, and can form no conception of the results that shall
ensue. The
man of genius who forsakes the equity that the humblest peasant has at
heart
will find all paths strange to him; and these will be stranger still
should he
overstep the limit his own sense of justice imposes; for the justice
that soars
aloft, keeping pace with the intellect, creates new boundaries around
all it
throws open, while at the same time strengthening and rendering more
insurmountable still the ancient barriers of instinct. The moment we
cross the
primitive frontier of equity all things seem to fail us; one falsehood
gives
birth to a hundred, and treachery returns to us through a thousand
channels. If
justice be in us we may march along boldly, for there are certain
things to
which the basest cannot be false; but if injustice possess us we must
beware of
the justest of men, for there are things to which even these cannot
remain
faithful. As our physical organism was devised for existence in the
atmosphere
of our globe, so is our moral organism devised for existence in
justice. Every
faculty craves for it, is more intimately bound up with it than with
the laws
of gravitation, of light or heat; and to throw ourselves into injustice
is to
plunge headlong into the hostile and the unknown. All that is in us has
been
placed there with a view to justice; all things tend thither and urge
us
towards it; whereas when we harbour injustice we battle against our own
strength; and at last, at the hour of inevitable punishment, when,
prostrate,
weeping, and penitent, we recognise that events, the sky, the universe,
the invisible,
are all in rebellion, all justly in league against us, then may we
truly say,
not that these are, or ever have been, just, but that we,
notwithstanding
ourselves, have contrived to remain just even in injustice. [19] We affirm that nature is absolutely
indifferent to
our morality, and that were this morality to command us to kill our
neighbour,
or to do him the utmost possible harm, nature would aid us in this no
less than
in our endeavour to comfort or serve him. She would as often seem to
reward us
for having made him suffer as for our kindness towards him. Are we
entitled to
conclude from this that nature has no morality — using the word in its
most
limited sense as meaning the logical, inevitable subordination of the
means to
the accomplishment of a general mission? That is a question to which we
must
not too hastily reply. We know nothing of nature’s aim, or whether she
have an
aim. We know nothing of her consciousness, or
whether she
have a consciousness; of her thoughts, or whether she think at all. It
is with
her deeds and her manner of doing that we are solely concerned. And in
these we
find the same contradiction between our morality and nature’s mode of
action as
exists between our consciousness and the instincts that nature has
planted within
us. For this consciousness, though in ultimate analysis due to her
also, has
nevertheless been formed by ourselves, and basing itself upon the
loftiest
human morality, offers an ever stronger opposition to the desires of
instinct.
Were we to listen only to these last, we should act in all things like
nature,
which would always seem to justify the triumph of the stronger, the
victory of
the least scrupulous and best equipped, and this in the midst of the
most
inexcusable wars, the most flagrant acts of injustice or cruelty. Our
one
object would be our own personal triumph; nor should we pay the least
heed to
the rights or sufferings of our victims, to their innocence or beauty,
moral or
intellectual superiority. But, in that case, why has nature placed
within us a
consciousness and a sense of justice that have prevented us from
desiring the
things that she desires? Or is it we ourselves who have placed them
there? Are
we capable of deriving from within us something that is not in nature;
are we
capable of giving abnormal development to a force that opposes her
force; and
if we possess this power, must she not have reasons of her own for
permitting
us to possess it? Why should there be only in us, and nowhere else in
the
world, these two irreconcilable tendencies that in every man are
incessantly at
strife, and victorious in turn? Would one have been dangerous without
the
other? Would it have overstepped its goal, perhaps; would the desire
for
conquest, unchecked by the sense of justice, have led us to
annihilation, as
the sense of justice without the desire for conquest might have induced
inertia? But which of these two tendencies is the more natural and
necessary,
which is the narrower and which the vaster, which is provisional and
which
eternal? Where shall we learn which one we should combat and which one
encourage? Ought we to conform to the law that is incontestably the
more
general, or should we cherish in our heart a law that is evidently
exceptional?
Are there circumstances under which we have the right to go forth in
search of
the apparent ideal of life? Is it our duty to follow the morality of
the
species or race, which seems irresistible to us, being one of the
visible sides
of nature’s obscure and unknown intentions; or is it essential that the
individual
should maintain and develop within him a morality entirely opposed to
that of
the race or species whereof he forms part? [20] The truth is that the question which
confronts us
here is only another form of the one which lies at the root of
evolutionary
morality, and is probably scientifically unsolvable. Evolutionary
morality
bases itself on the justice of nature — though it dare not speak out
the word;
on the justice of nature, which imposes upon each individual the good
or evil
consequences of his own character and his own actions. But when, on the
other
hand, it is necessary for evolutionary morality to justify actions
which, although
intrinsically unjust, are necessary for the prosperity of the species,
it falls
back upon what it reluctantly terms nature’s indifference or injustice.
Here we
have two unknown aims, that of humanity and that of mankind; and these,
wrapped
as they are in a mystery that may some day perhaps pass away, would
seem to be
irreconcilable in our mind. Essentially, all these questions resolve
themselves
into one, which is of the utmost importance to our contemporary
morality. The
race would appear to be becoming conscious, prematurely it may be, and
perhaps
disastrously, not, we will say, of its rights, for that problem is
still in
suspense, but of the fact that morality does not enter into certain
actions
that go to make history. This disquieting consciousness would seem
to be
slowly invading our individual life. Thrice, and more or less in the
course of
one year, has this question confronted us, and assumed vast
proportions: in the
matter of America’s crushing defeat of Spain (although here the issues
are confused,
for the Spaniards had been guilty of so many acts of injustice in the
past,
besides their present blunders, that the problem becomes very
involved); in the
case of an innocent man sacrificed to the preponderating interest of
his
country; and in the iniquitous war of the Transvaal. It is true that
the
phenomenon is not altogether without precedent. Man has always
endeavoured to
justify his injustice; and when human justice offered him no excuse or
pretext,
he found in the will of the gods a law superior to the justice of man.
But our
excuse or pretext of to-day is fraught with the more peril to our
morality
inasmuch as it reposes on a law, or at least a habit, of nature, that
is far
more real, more incontestable and universal than the will of an
ephemeral and
local god. Which shall prevail in the end, justice or
force?
Does force contain an unknown justice that will absorb our human
justice, or is
the impulse of justice within us, that would seem to resist blind
force,
actually no more than a devious emanation from that force, tending to
the same
end; and is it only the point of deviation that escapes us? This is not
a
question that we can answer, we who ourselves form part of the mystery
we seek
to solve; the reply could come only from one who might be gazing upon
us from
the heights of another world: one who should have learned the aim of
the
universe and the destiny of man. In the meanwhile, if we say that
nature is
right, we say that the instinct of justice, which she has placed in us,
and
which therefore also is nature, is wrong; whereas if we approve this
instinct,
our approval is necessarily derived from the exercise of the very
faculty that
is called in question. [21] That is true; but it is no less true that
the
endeavour to sum up the world in a syllogism is one of the oldest and
vainest
habits of man. In the region of the unknown and unknowable,
logic-chopping has
its perils; and here all our doubts would seem to arise from another
hazardous
syllogism. We tell ourselves — boldly at times, but more often in a
whisper —
that we are nature’s children, and bound therefore in all things to
conform to
her laws and copy her example. And since nature regards justice with
indifference, since she has another aim, which is the sustaining, the
renewing,
the incessant development, of life, it follows . . . So far we have not
formulated the conclusion, or, at least, this conclusion has not yet
dared
openly to force its way into our morality; but, although its influence
has
hitherto only been remotely felt in that familiar sphere which includes
our
relations, our friends, and our immediate surroundings, it is slowly
penetrating into the vast and desolate region whither we relegate all
those
whom we know not and see not, who for us have no name. It is already to
be
found at the root of many of our actions; it has entered our politics,
our
industry, our commerce; indeed it affects almost all we do from the
moment we
emerge from the narrow circle of our domestic hearth, the only place
for the
majority of men where a little veritable justice is still to be found,
a little
benevolence, a little love. It will call itself economic or social law,
evolution, competition, struggle for life; it will masquerade under a
thousand
names, forever perpetrating the selfsame wrong. And yet nothing can be
less
legitimate than such a conclusion. Apart from the fact that we might
with equal
justification reverse the syllogism, and cause it to declare that there
must be
a certain justice in nature, since we, her children, are just, we need
only
consider it as it stands to realise how doubtful and contestable is at
least
one of its two premisses. We have seen in the preceding chapters
that nature
does not appear to be just from our point of view; but we have
absolutely no
means of judging whether she be not just from her own. The fact that
she pays
no heed to the morality of our actions does not warrant the inference
that she
has no morality, or that ours is the only one there can be. We are
entitled to
say that she cares not whether our intentions be good or evil, but we
have not
the right to conclude that she has therefore no morality and no equity;
for
that would be tantamount to affirming that there are no more mysteries
or
secrets, and that we know all the laws of the universe, its origin and
its end.
Her mode of action is different from our own, but, I say it once more,
we know
not what her reason may be for acting in this different fashion; and we
have no
right to imitate what seems iniquitous and cruel to us so long as we
have no precise
knowledge of the profound and salutary reasons that may underlie such
action.
What is the aim of nature? Whither do the worlds tend that stretch
across
eternity? Where does consciousness begin, and is its only form that
which it
assumes in ourselves? At what point do physical laws become moral laws?
Is life
unintelligent? Have we sounded all the depths of nature, and is it only
in our
cerebro-spinal system that she becomes mind? And finally, what is
justice when
viewed from other heights? Is the intention necessarily at its centre;
and can
no regions exist where intentions no longer shall count? We should have to
answer these
questions, and many others, before we should be able to tell whether
nature be
just or unjust from the point of view of masses whose vastness
corresponds to
her own. She disposes of a future, a space, of which we can form no
conception;
and in these there exists, it may be, a justice proportioned to her
duration,
her extent and her aim, even as our own instinct of justice is
proportioned to
the duration and narrow circle of our own life. The wrong that she may
for
centuries commit she has centuries in which to repair; but we who have
only a
few days before us, what right have we to imitate what our eye cannot
see,
understand or follow? By what standard are we to judge her, if we look
away
from the passing hour? For instance, considering only the imperceptible
speck
that we form in the worlds, and disregarding the immensity that
surrounds us,
we are wholly ignorant of all that concerns our possible life beyond
the tomb;
and we forget that, in the present state of our knowledge, nothing
authorises
us to affirm that there may not be a kind of more or less conscious,
more or
less responsible, after-life, that shall in no way depend on the
decisions of
an external will. He would indeed be rash who should venture to affirm
that
nothing survives, either in us or in others, of the efforts of our good
intentions and the acquirements of our mind. It may be — and serious
experiments, though they do not seem to prove the phenomenon, may still
allow
us to class it among scientific possibilities — it may be that a part
of our
personality, of our nervous force, may escape dissolution. How vast a
future
would then be thrown open to the laws that unite cause to effect, and
that
always end by creating justice when they come into contact with the
human soul,
and have centuries before them! Let us not forget that nature at least
is
logical, even though we call her unjust; and were we to resolve on
injustice,
our difficulty would be that we must also be logical; and when logic
comes into
touch with our thoughts and our feelings, our intentions and passions,
what is
there that differentiates it from justice? [22] Let us form no too hasty conclusion; too
many points
are still uncertain. Should we seek to imitate what we term the
injustice of
nature, we would run the risk of imitating and fostering only the
injustice
that is in ourselves. When we say that nature is unjust, we are in
effect
complaining of her indifference to our own little virtues, our own
little
intentions, our own little deeds of heroism; and it is our vanity far
more than
our sense of equity that considers itself aggrieved. Our morality is
proportionate
to our stature and our restricted destiny; nor have we the right to
forsake it
because it is not on the scale of the immensity and infinite destiny of
the
universe. And further, should it even be proved that
nature is
unjust at all points, the other question remains intact: whether the
command be
laid upon man to follow nature in her injustice. Here we shall do well
to let
our own consciousness speak, rather than listen to a voice so
formidable that
we hear not a word it utters, and know not even whether words there be.
Reason
and instinct tell us that it is right to follow the counsels of nature;
but
they tell us also that we should not follow those counsels when they
clash with
another instinct within us, one that is no less profound: the instinct
of the
just and the unjust. And if instincts do indeed draw very near to the
truth of
nature, and must be respected by us in the degree of the force that is
in them,
this one is perhaps the strongest of all, for it has struggled alone
against
all the others combined, and still persists within us. Nor is this the
hour to
reject it. Until other certitudes reach us, it behoves us, who are men,
to
continue, just in the human way and the human sphere. We do not see far
enough,
or clearly enough, to be just in another sphere. Let us not venture
into a kind
of abyss, out of which races and peoples to come may perhaps find a
passage;
but whereinto man, in so far as he is man, must not seek to penetrate.
The
injustice of nature ends by becoming justice for the race; she has time
before
her, she can wait, her injustice is of her girth. But for us it is too
overwhelming, and our days are too few. Let us be satisfied that force
should
reign in the universe, but equity in our heart. Though the race be
irresistibly, and perhaps justly, unjust, though even the crowd appear
possessed of rights denied to the isolated man, and commit on occasions
great,
inevitable, and salutary crimes, it is still the duty of each
individual of the
race, of every member of the crowd, to remain just, while ever adding
to, and
sustaining, the consciousness within him. Nor shall we be entitled to
abandon
this duty till all the reasons of the great apparent injustice be known
to us;
and those that are given us now, preservation of the species,
reproduction, and
selection of the strongest, ablest, “fittest,” are not sufficient to
warrant so
frightful a change. Let each one try by all means to become the
strongest, most
skilful, the best adapted to the necessities of the life that he cannot
transform; but, so far, the qualities that shall enable him to conquer,
that
shall give the fullest play to his moral power and his intelligence,
and shall
truly make him the happiest, most skilful, the strongest and “fittest"
—
these qualities are precisely the ones that are the most human, the
most
honourable and the most just. [23] “Within me there is more,” runs the fine
device
inscribed on the beams and pediment of an old patrician mansion at
Bruges,
which every traveller visits; filling a corner of one of those tender
and
melancholy quays, that are as forlorn and lifeless as though they
existed only
on canvas. And so too might man exclaim, “Within me there is more;”
every law
of morality, every intelligible mystery. There may be many others,
above and
below us; but if these are to remain forever unknown, they become for
us as
though they existed not; and should their existence one day be revealed
to us,
it can only be because they already are in us, already are ours.
“Within me
there is more;" and we are entitled to add, perhaps: "I have nothing
to fear from that which is in me.” This much at least is certain: that the
one active,
inhabited region of the mystery of justice is to be found within
ourselves.
Other regions lack consistency; they are probably imaginary, and must
inevitably be deserted and sterile. They may have furnished mankind
with
illusions that served some purpose, but not always without doing harm;
and
though we may scarcely be entitled to demand that all illusions should
be
destroyed, they should at least not be too manifestly opposed to our
conception
of the universe. To-day we seek in all things the illusion of truth. It is not the last, perhaps, or the best,
or the only
one possible; but it is the one which we at present regard as the most
honourable
and the most necessary. Let us limit ourselves therefore to recognising
the
admirable love of justice and truth that exists in the heart of man.
Proceeding
thus, yielding admiration only where it is incontestably due, we shall
gradually acquire some knowledge of this passion, which is the
distinguishing
mark of man; and one thing, most important of all, we shall most
undoubtedly
learn — the means whereby we can purify it, and still further increase
it. As
we observe its incessant activity in the depths of our heart, the only
temple
where it can truly be active; as we watch it blending with all that we
think,
and feel, and do, we shall quickly discover which are the things that
throw
light upon it, and which those that plunge it in darkness, which are
the things
that guide it and which those that lead it astray; we shall learn what
nourishes and what atrophies, what attacks and what defends. Is justice no more than the human instinct
of
preservation and defence? Is it the purest product of our reason; or
rather to
be regarded as composed of a number of those sentimental forces which
so often
are right, though directly opposed to our reason — forces that in
themselves
are a kind of unconscious, vaster reason, to which our conscious reason
invariably accords its startled approval when it has reached the
heights whence
those kindly feelings long had beheld what itself was unable to see? Is
justice
dependent on intellect, or rather on character? Questions these that
are
perhaps not idle if we indeed would seek to know what steps we must
take to
invest with all its radiance and all its power the love of justice that
is the
central jewel of the human soul. All men love justice, but not with the
same
ardent, fierce, exclusive love; nor have they all the same scruples,
the same
sensitiveness, or the same deep conviction. We meet people of highly
developed
intellect, in whom the sense of what is just and unjust is yet
infinitely less
delicate, less clearly marked, than in others whose intellect would
seem to be
mediocre; for here a great part is played by that little known,
ill-defined
side of ourselves that we term the character. And yet it is difficult
to tell
how much more or less unconscious intellect must of necessity go with
the
character that is unaffectedly honest. The point before us, however, is
to
learn how best to illumine, and increase within us, our desire for
justice; and
it is certain that, at the start, our character is less directly
influenced by
our desire for justice than is our intellect, the development of which
this
desire in a large measure controls; and the cooperation of the
intellect, which
recognises and encourages our good intention, is necessary for this to
penetrate into, and mould, our character. That portion of our love of
justice,
therefore, which depends on our character, will benefit by its passage
through
the intellect; for in proportion as the intellect rises, and acquires
enlightenment, will it succeed in mastering, enlightening, and
transforming our
instincts and our feelings. But let us no longer believe that this
love must be
sought in a kind of superhuman, and often inhuman, infinite. None of
the
grandeur and beauty that this infinite may possess would fall to its
portion;
it would only be incoherent, inactive, and vague. Whereas by seeking it
in
ourselves, where it truly is; by observing it there, listening to it,
marking
how it profits by every acquirement of our mind, every joy and sorrow
of our
heart, we soon shall learn what we best had do to purify and increase
it. [24] Our task within these limits will be
sufficiently
long and mysterious. To increase and purify within us the desire for
justice:
how shall this thing be done? We have some vague conception of the
ideal that
we would approach; but how changeable still, and illusory, is this
ideal! It is
lessened by all that is still unknown to us in the universe, by all
that we do
not perceive, or perceive incompletely, by all that we question too
superficially. It is hedged round by the most insidious dangers; it
falls victim
to the strangest oblivion, the most inconceivable blunders. Of all our
ideals
it is the one that we should watch with the greatest care and anxiety,
with the
most passionate, pious eagerness and solicitude. What seems
irreproachably just
to us at the moment is probably the merest fraction of what would seem
just,
could we regard it from another place. We need only compare what we
were doing
yesterday with what we do to-day; and what we do to-day would appear
full of
faults against equity were it granted to us to rise still higher and
compare it
with what we shall do tomorrow. There needs but a passing event, a
thought that
rises, a duty to ourselves that takes definite form, an unexpected
responsibility that is suddenly made clear, for the whole organisation
of our
inward justice to totter and be transformed. Slow as our advance may
have been,
we still should find it impossible to begin life again in the midst of
many a
sorrow whereof we were the involuntary cause, many a discouragement to
which we
unconsciously gave rise; and yet, when these things came into being
around us,
we appeared to be in the right, and did not consider ourselves unjust.
And even
so are we convinced to-day of our excellent intentions; even so do we
tell
ourselves that we are the cause of no suffering and no tears, that we
stay not
a murmur of happiness, shorten no moment of peace or of love; and it
may be
that there passes, unperceived of us, to our right or our left, an
illimitable
injustice that spreads over three fourths of our life. [25] I chanced to-day to take up a copy of the
“Arabian
Nights" in the very remarkable translation recently published by Dr.
Mardrus; and I marvelled at the extraordinary picture it gives of the
ancient,
long-vanished civilisations. Not in the Odyssey or the Bible, in
Xenophon or
Plutarch, could their teaching be more clearly set forth. There is one
story
that the Sultana Schahrazade tells — it is one of the very finest the
volume
contains — that reveals a life as pure and admirable as mankind has
ever known;
a life replete with beauty, happiness, and love; spontaneous and vivid,
intelligent, flourishing, and refined; an abundant life that, to a
certain
point, comes as near truth as a life well can. It is, in many respects,
almost
as perfect in its moral as in its material civilisation. And the
pillars on
which this incomparable structure of happiness rests — like pillars of
light
supporting the light — are formed of ideas of justice so delicate,
counsels of
wisdom so deeply penetrating, that we of to-day, who are less fine in
grain,
less eager and buoyant, have lost the power to formulate or to discern
them.
And for all that, this abode of felicity, that harbours a moral life so
active
and vigorous, so noble, so graciously grave, — this palace, wherein the
purest
and holiest wisdom governs the pleasures of rejoicing mankind — is in
its
entirety based on so great an injustice, is enclosed by so vast, so
profound,
so frightful an iniquity, that the wretchedest man of us all would
shrink in
dismay from its glittering, gem-bestrewn threshold. But of this
iniquity they
who linger in that marvellous dwelling have not the remotest suspicion.
It
would seem that they never draw near to a window; or that, should one
by some
chance fly open and reveal to their sorrowful gaze the misery strewn in
the
midst of the revels and feasting, they still would be blind to the
crime which
was infinitely more revolting, infinitely more monstrous, than the most
appalling poverty: the crime of the slavery, and the even more terrible
degradation, of their women. For these, however exalted their position,
and at
the moment even when they are speaking to the men round about them of
goodness
and justice; when they are reminding them of their most touching and
generous
duties — these women never are more than mere objects of pleasure, to
be
bought, or sold, or given away, in a moment of gratitude, ostentation
or
drunkenness, to any barbarous or hideous master. [26] “They tell us,” says the beautiful slave
Nozhatan,
as, concealed behind a curtain of silk and of pearls, she speaks to
Prince
Sharkan and the wise men of the kingdom, — “they tell us that the
Khalif Omar
set forth one night, in the company of the venerable Aslam Abou-Zeid,
and that
he beheld, far away from his palace, a fire that was burning; and drew
near, as
he thought that his presence might perhaps be of service. And he saw a
poor
woman who was kindling wood underneath a caldron, and by her side were
two
little wretched children, groaning most piteously. And Omar said,
'Peace unto
thee, O woman! What dost thou here, alone in the night and the cold?' And she answered, ‘Lord, I am making this
water to boil, that my children may drink, who perish of hunger and
cold; but
for the misery we have to bear, Allah will surely one day ask reckoning
of Omar
the Khalif.’ And the Khalif, who was in disguise, was much moved, and
he said
to her, 'But dost thou think, O woman, that Omar can know of thy
wretchedness,
seeing that he does not relieve it?' And she answered, 'Wherefore,
then, is Omar
the Khalif if he be unaware of the misery of his people and of each one
of his
subjects?' Then the Khalif was silent and he said to Aslam Abou-Zeid,
'Let us
go quickly from hence.’ And he hastened until he had reached the
storehouse of
his kitchens, and he entered therein and drew forth a sack of flour
from the
midst of the other sacks, and also a jar that was filled to the brim
with sheep
fat, and he said to Abou-Zeid, 'O Abou-Zeid, help thou me to charge
these on my
back.’ But Abou-Zeid refused, and he cried, 'Suffer that I carry them
upon my
back O Commander of the Faithful.’ And Omar said calmly to him, 'Wilt
thou
also, O Abou-Zeid, bear the weight of my sins on the Day of
Resurrection?’ And
Abou-Zeid was obliged to lay the jar filled with fat and the sack of
flour on
the Khalif’s back. And Omar hastened, thus laden, until he had once
again
reached the poor woman; and he took of the flour, and he took of the
fat, and
placed these in the caldron over the fire; and with his own hands did
he then
get ready the food, and he quickened the fire with his breath; and as
he bent
over, his beard being long, the smoke from the wood forced its way
through the
beard of the Khalif. And at last, when the food was prepared, Omar
offered it
unto the woman and the two little children; and with his breath did he
cool the
food while these ate their fill. Then he left them the sack of flour
and the
jar of fat; and he went on his way and said unto Aslam Abou-Zeid, 'O
Abou-Zeid,
the light from this fire that I have beheld to-day has enlightened me
also.’
" [27] And it is thus that, a little further on,
there
speaks to a very wise king one of five pensive maidens whom this king
is
invited to buy. “Know thou, O King,” she says; “that the most beautiful
deed
one can do is the deed that is disinterested. And so do they tell us
that in
Israel once were two brothers, and that one asked the other, ‘Of all
the deeds
thou hast done, which was the most wicked?' And his brother replied,
‘This: as
I passed by a hen-roost one day I stretched out my arm and I seized a
chicken
and strangled it, and then flung it back into the roost. That is the
wickedest
deed of my life. And thou, O my brother, what is thy wickedest action?'
And he
answered, ‘That I prayed to Allah one day to demand a favour of him.
For it is
only when the soul is simply uplifted on high that prayer can be
beautiful.’
" And one of her companions, captive and
slave like
herself, also speaks to the king. “Learn to know thyself!" she says.
“Learn to know thyself! And do thou not act till then. And do thou then
only
act in accordance with all thy desires, but having great care always
that thou
do not injure thy neighbour.” To this last formula our morality of
to-day has
nothing to add; nor can we conceive a precept that shall be more
complete. At
most we could widen the meaning of the word “neighbour,” and expand,
extend,
and raise, render somewhat more subtle and more elastic, that of the
word
“injure.” And the book in which these words are found is a monument of
horror,
notwithstanding all its flowers and all its wisdom; a monument of
horror and
blood and tears, of despotism and slavery. And they are all slaves,
those who
pronounce these words. A merchant buys them, I know not where, and
sells them
to some old hag who teaches them, or causes them to be taught,
philosophy,
poetry, all Eastern sciences, in order that one day they may become
gifts
worthy of a king. And when their education is finished, and their
beauty and
wisdom call forth the admiration of all who approach them, the
industrious,
prudent old woman does indeed offer them to a very wise, very just
king. And
when this very wise, very just king has taken their virginity from them
and
seeks other loves, he will probably bestow them (I have forgotten the
end of
this particular story, but it is the invariable destiny of all the
heroines of
these marvellous legends) on his viziers. And these viziers will give
them away
in exchange for a vase of perfume, for a belt that is studded with
jewels, or
perhaps despatch to a distant country, to conciliate a powerful
protector, or a
hideous, but dreaded, rival. And these women, so fully conscious of
themselves,
whose gaze can penetrate so deeply into the consciousness of others;
these
women who forever are pondering the loftiest, grandest problems of
justice, of
the morality of men and of nations, never throw one questioning glance
on their
fate, or for an instant suspect the abominable injustice whereof they
are the
victims. Nor do those suspect it either who listen to them, and love
and admire
and understand them. And we who marvel at this — we who also reflect on
justice
and virtue, on pity and love — are we so sure that they who come after
us shall
not some day find, in our present social condition, a spectacle no less
disconcerting? [28] It is difficult for us to imagine what the
ideal
justice will be, for every thought of ours that tends towards it is
clogged by
the injustice wherein we still live. Who shall say what new laws and
relations
will stand revealed when the misfortunes and inequalities due to the
action of
man shall have been swept away; when, in accordance with the principles
of
evolutionary morality, each individual shall “reap the results, good or
bad, of
his own nature, and of the consequences that ensue from that nature?"
At
present things happen otherwise; and we may unhesitatingly declare
that, as far
as the material condition of the vast bulk of mankind is concerned, the
connection between conduct and consequences — to use Spencer’s formula
— exists
only in the most ludicrous, arbitrary, and iniquitous fashion. Is there
not
something of audacity in our imagining that our thoughts can possibly
be just
when the body of each one of us is steeped to the neck in injustice?
And from
this injustice no man is free, be it to his loss or his gain; there is
not one
whose efforts are not disproportionately rewarded, receiving either too
much or
too little; not one who is not either advantaged or handicapped. And
endeavour
as we may to detach our mind from this inveterate injustice, this
lingering
trace of the sub-human morality needful for primitive races, it is idle
to
think that our thoughts can be as strenuous, as independent or clear,
as they
might have been had the last vestige of this injustice disappeared; it
is idle
to think that they can achieve the same result. The side of the human
mind that
can attain a region loftier than reality is necessarily timid and
hesitating.
Human thought is capable of many things; it has, in the course of time,
brought
startling improvement to bear upon what seemed immutable in the species
or the
race. But even at the moment when it is pondering the transformation of
which
it has caught a distant glimpse, the improvement that it so eagerly
desires,
even then it is still thinking, feeling, seeing, like the thing that it
seeks
to alter; even then it lies captive beneath the yoke. All its efforts
notwithstanding, it is practically that which it would change. For the
mind of
man lacks the power to forecast the future; it has been formed rather
to explain,
judge, and co-ordinate that which was; to help, foster, and make known
what
already exists but so far cannot be seen; and when it ventures into
what is not
yet it will rarely produce anything very salutary or very enduring. And
the
influence of the social condition in which we exist lies heavy upon it.
How can
we frame a satisfactory idea of justice, and ponder it loyally, and
with the
needful tranquillity, when injustice surrounds us on every side? Before
we can
study justice, or speak of it with advantage, it must become what it is
capable
of being: a social force, irreproachable and actual. At present all we
can do
is to invoke its unconscious, secret, and, as it were, almost
imperceptible
effects. We contemplate it from the shores of human injustice; never
yet has it
been granted us to gaze on the open sea beneath the illimitable,
inviolate sky
of a conscience without reproach. If men had at least done all that it
was
possible for them to do in their own domain, they would then have the
right to
go further, and question elsewhere; and their thoughts would probably
be
clearer, were their consciences more at ease. [29] And further, a heavy reproach lies on us,
and chills
our ardour, whenever we try to grow better, to increase our knowledge,
our
love, our forgiveness. Though we purify our consciousness and ennoble
our
thoughts, though we strive to render life softer and sweeter for those
who are
near us, all our efforts halt at our threshold, and have no influence
on what
lies outside our door; and the moment we leave our home we feel that we
have
done nothing, that there is nothing for us to do, and that we are
taking part,
ourselves notwithstanding, in the great anonymous injustice. Is it not
almost
ludicrous that we, who within our four walls strive to be noble and
faithful,
pitiful, simple, and loyal; we whose consciousness balances the nicest,
most
delicate problems, and rejects even the suspicion of a bitter thought,
have no
sooner gone into the street, and met faces that are unfamiliar, than,
at that
very instant, and without the least possibility of our having it
otherwise, all
pity, equity, love should be completely ignored by us? What dignity,
what
loyalty, can there be in this double life, so wise and humane, uplifted
and
thoughtful, this side the threshold, and beyond it so callous, so
instinctive
and pitiless? For it is enough that we should feel the cold a little
less than
the labourer who passes by, that we should be better fed or clad than
he, that
we should buy any object that is not strictly indispensable, and we
have
unconsciously returned, through a thousand byways, to the ruthless act
of
primitive man despoiling his weaker brother. There is no single
privilege we
enjoy but close investigation will prove it to be the result of a
perhaps very
remote abuse of power, an unknown violence or ruse of long ago; and all
these
we set in motion again as we sit at our table, stroll idly through the
town, or
lie at night in a bed that our own hands have not made. Nay, what is
even the
leisure that enables us to improve, to grow more compassionate and
gentler, to
think more fraternally of the injustice others endure — what is this,
in truth,
but the ripest fruit of the great injustice? [30] These scruples, I know, must not be
carried too far;
they would either induce a spirit of useless revolt, possibly
disastrous to the
species whose mild and mighty sluggishness we are bound to respect; or
they
would lead us back to I know not what mystic, inert renouncement,
directly
opposed to the most evident and unchanging desires of life. Life has
laws that
we call inevitable; but we are already becoming more sparing in our use
of the
word. And here especially do we note the change that has come over the
attitude
of the wise and upright man. Marcus Aurelius — than whom perhaps none
ever
craved more earnestly for justice, or possessed a soul more wisely
impressionable, more nobly sensitive — Marcus Aurelius never asked
himself what
might be happening outside that admirable little circle of light
wherein his
virtue and consciousness, his divine meekness and piety, had gathered
those who
were near him, his friends and his servants. Infinite iniquity, he knew
full
well, stretched around him on every side; but with this he had no
concern. To
him it seemed a thing that must be, mysterious and sacred as the mighty
ocean;
the boundless domain of the gods, of fatality, of laws unknown and
superior,
irresistible, irresponsible, and eternal. It did not lessen his
courage; on the
contrary, it enhanced his confidence, his concentration, and spurred
him
upwards, like the flame that, confined to a narrow area, rises higher
and
higher, alone in the night, urged on by the darkness. He accepted the
decree of
fate, that allotted slavery to the bulk of mankind. Sorrowfully, but
with full
conviction, did he submit to the irrevocable law; wherein he once again
gave
proof of his piety and his virtue. He retired into himself; and there,
in a
kind of sunless, motionless void, became still more just, still more
humane.
And in each succeeding century do we find a similar ardour,
self-centred and
solitary, among those who were wise and good. The name of more than one
immovable law might change, but its infinite part remained ever the
same; and
each one regarded it with the like resigned and chastened melancholy.
But we of
to-day — what course are we to pursue? We know that iniquity is no
longer
necessary. We have invaded the region of the gods, of destiny and
unknown laws.
These may still control disease and accident, perhaps, no less than the
tempest, the lightning-flash, and most of the mysteries of death; we
have not
yet penetrated to them; but we are well aware that poverty,
wretchedness,
hopeless toil, slavery, famine, are completely outside their domain. It
is we
who organise these, we who maintain and distribute them. These
frightful
scourges, that have grown so familiar, are wielded by us alone; and
belief in
their superhuman origin is becoming rarer and rarer. The religious,
impassable
ocean that excused and protected the retreat into himself of the sage
and the
man of good, now only exists as a vague recollection. To-day Marcus
Aurelius
could no longer say with the same serenity: “They go in search of
refuges, of
rural cottages, of mountains, of the sea-shore; thou too art wont to
cherish an
eager desire for these things. But is this not the act of an ignorant,
unskilled man, seeing that it is granted thee at whatever hour thou
pleasest to
retire within thyself? It is not possible for man to discover a retreat
more
tranquil, less disturbed by affairs, than that which he finds in his
soul;
especially if he have within him those things the contemplation of
which
suffices to procure immediate enjoyment of the perfect calm, which is
no other,
to my mind, than the perfect agreement of soul.” Other matters concern us to-day than this
agreement
of soul; or let us rather say that what we have to do is to bring into
agreement there that from which the soul of Marcus Aurelius was free, —
three-fourths of the sorrows of mankind, in a word, which have become
real to
us, intelligible, human, urgent, and are no longer regarded as the
inexplicable, immutable, intangible decrees of fate. [31] This does not imply, however, that we
should abandon
the old sage’s desire for “agreement;” and even though we may not be
entitled
to expect such perfect “agreement"
as they derived from their pardonable egoism, we may still look for
agreement
of a provisional, conditional kind. And although such “agreement" be
not
the last word of morality, it is none the less indispensable that we
should
begin by being as just as we possibly can within ourselves and to those
round
about us, our neighbours, our friends, and our servants. It is at the
moment
when we have become absolutely just to these, and within our own
consciousness,
that we realise our great injustice to all the others. The method of
being more
practically just towards these last is not yet known to us; to return
to great,
heroic renouncements would effect but little, for these are incapable
of
unanimous action, and would probably run counter to the profoundest
laws of
nature, which rejects renouncement in every form save that of maternal
love. This practical justice, therefore, remains
the secret
of the race. Of such secrets it has many, which it reveals one by one,
at such
moments of history as become truly critical; and the solutions it
offers to
insuperable difficulties are almost always unexpected, and of curious
simplicity. The hour approaches perhaps when it will speak once more.
Let us
hope, without being too sanguine; for we must bear in mind that
humanity has
yet by no means emerged from the period of “sacrificed generations.”
History
has known no others; and it is possible that, to the end of time, all
generations may call themselves sacrificed. Nevertheless, it cannot be
denied
that the sacrifices, however unjust and useless they still may be, are
growing
ever less inhuman and less inevitable; and that the laws which govern
them are
becoming better and better known, and would seem to draw nearer and
nearer to
those that a lofty mind might accept without being pitiless. [32] It must be admitted, however, that a
majestic,
redoubtable slowness attends the movements of these “ideas of the
species.”
Centuries had to pass by before it dawned upon primitive men, who fled
from
each other, or fought when they met at the mouth of their caverns, that
they
would do well to form into groups, and unite in defence against the
mighty
enemies threatening them from without. And besides, these “ideas" of
the
species will often be widely different from those that the wisest man
might
hold. They would seem to be independent, spontaneous, often based on
facts of
which no trace is shown by the human reason of the epoch that witnessed
their
birth; and indeed there is no graver or more disturbing problem before
the
moralist or sociologist than that of determining whether all his
efforts can
hasten by one hour or divert by one hair’s-breadth the decisions of the
great,
anonymous mass which proceeds, step by step, towards its indiscernible
goal. [33] Long ago — so long indeed that this is one
of the
first affirmations of science, when, quitting the bowels of the earth,
the
glaciers and grottoes, it ceased to call itself geology and
palæontology and
became the history of man — humanity passed through a crisis not wholly
unlike
that which now lies ahead of it, or is actually menacing it at the
moment; the
difference being only that in those days the dilemma seemed vastly more
tragic
and more unsolvable. It may truly be said that mankind never has known
a more
perilous or more decisive hour, or a period when it drew nearer its
ruin; and
the fact that we exist to-day would appear to be due to the unexpected
expedient
which saved the race at the moment when the scourge that fed on man’s
very
reason, on all that was best and most irresistible in his instinct of
justice
and injustice, was actually on the point of destroying the heroic
equilibrium
between the desire to live and the possibility of living. I refer to the acts of violence, rapine,
outrage,
murder, which were of natural occurrence among the earliest human
groups. These
crimes, which will probably have been of the most frightful
description, must
have very seriously endangered the existence of the race; for vengeance
is the
terrible, and, as it were, the epidemic form which the craving for
justice at
first assumes. Now this spirit of vengeance, abandoned to itself and
forever
multiplying, — revenge followed by the revenge of revenge, — would
finally have
engulfed, if not the whole of mankind, at least all those of the
earliest men
who were possessed of energy or pride. We find, however, that among
these
barbarous races, as among most of the existing savage tribes whose
habits are
known to us, there comes a time, usually at the period when their
weapons are
growing too deadly, when this vengeance suddenly halts before a
singular custom
known as the “blood-tribute,” or the “composition for murder,” which
allows the
homicide to escape the reprisals of the victim’s friends and relations
by
payment to them of an indemnity, that, from being arbitrary at the
start, soon
becomes strictly graduated. In the whole history of these infant
races, in whom
impulse and heroism were the predominant factors, there is nothing
stranger,
nothing more astounding, than this almost universal custom, which for
all its
ingenuity would appear almost too long-suffering and mercantile. May we
attribute it to the foresight of the chiefs? We find it in races among
whom
authority might almost be said to be entirely lacking. Did it originate
among
the old men, the thinkers, the sages, of the primitive groups? That is
not more
probable. For underlying this custom there is a thought which is at the
same
time higher and lower than could be the thought of an isolated prophet
or
genius of those barbarous days. The sage, the prophet, the genius —
above all,
the untrained genius — is rather inclined to carry to extremes the
generous and
heroic tendencies of the clan or epoch to which he belongs. He would
have
recoiled in disgust from this timid, cunning evasion of a natural and
sacred
revenge, from this odious traffic in friendship, fidelity, and love.
Nor is it
conceivable, on the other hand, that he should have attained sufficient
loftiness of spirit to be able to let his gaze travel beyond the
noblest and
most incontestable duties of the moment, and to behold only the
superior
interest of the tribe or the race: that mysterious desire for life
which the
wisest of the wise among us to-day are generally unable to perceive or
to
justify until they have wrought grave and painful conquest over their
isolated
reason and their heart. No, it was not the thought of man which
found the
solution. On the contrary, it was the unconsciousness of the mass,
compelled to
act in self-defence against thoughts too intrinsically, individually
human to
satisfy the irreducible exigencies of life on this earth. The species
is
extremely patient, extremely long-suffering. It will bear as long as it
can and
carry as far as it can the burden which reason, the desire for
improvement, the
imagination, the passions, vices, virtues, and feelings natural to man,
may
combine to impose upon it. But at the moment when this burden becomes
too
overwhelming, and disaster threatens, the species will, instantaneously
and
with the utmost indifference, fling it aside. It is careless as to the
means;
it will adopt the one that is nearest, the simplest, most practical,
being
doubtless perfectly satisfied that its own idea is the justest and
best. And of
ideas it has only one, which is that it wishes to live; and truly this
idea
surpasses all the heroism, all the generous dreams, that may have
reposed in
the burden which it has discarded. And indeed, in the history of human
reason, the
greatest and the justest thoughts are not always those which attain the
loftiest heights. It happens somewhat with the thoughts of men as with
a
fountain; for it is only because the water has been imprisoned and
escapes
through a narrow opening that it soars so proudly into the air. As it
issues
from this opening and hurls itself towards the sky, it would seem to
despise
the great, illimitable, motionless lake that stretches out far beneath
it. And
yet, say what one will, it is the lake that is right. For all its
apparent
motionlessness, for all its silence, it is tranquilly accomplishing the
immense
and normal task of the most important element of our globe; and the jet
of
water is merely a curious incident, which soon returns into the
universal
scheme. To us, the species is the great, unerring lake; and this even
from the
point of view of the superior human reason that it would seem at times
to
offend. Its idea is the vastest of all, and contains every other; it
embraces
limitless time and space. And does not each day that goes by reveal
more and
more clearly to us that the vastest idea, no matter where it reside,
always
ends by becoming the most just and most reasonable, the wisest, and the
most
beautiful? [34] There are times when we ask ourselves
whether it
might not be well for humanity that its destinies should be governed by
the
superior men among us, the great sages, rather than by the instincts of
the
species, that are always so slow, and often so cruel. It is doubtful whether this question could
be
answered to-day in quite the same fashion as formerly. It would surely
have
been highly dangerous to confide the destinies of the species to Plato
or
Aristotle, Marcus Aurelius, Shakespeare, or Montesquieu. At the very
worst
moments of the French Revolution, the fate of the people was in the
hands of
philosophers of none too mean an order. It cannot be denied, however,
that in
our time the habits of the thinker have undergone a great change. He
has ceased
to be speculative or utopian: he is no longer exclusively intuitive. In
politics as in literature, in philosophy as in all the sciences, he
displays
less imagination, but his powers as an observer have grown. He inclines
rather
to concentrate his attention on the thing that is, to study it and
strive at
its organisation, than to precede it, or endeavour to create what is
not yet,
or never shall be. And therefore he may possibly have some claim to
more
authoritative utterance; nor would so much danger attend his more
direct
intervention. It must be admitted, however, that there is no greater
likelihood
now than in former times of such intervention being permitted him. Nay,
there
is less, perhaps; for having become more circumspect and less blinded
by narrow
convictions, he will be less audacious, less imperious, and less
impatient. And
yet it is possible that, finding himself in natural sympathy with the
species
which he is content merely to observe, he will by slow degrees acquire
more and
more influence; so that here again, in ultimate analysis, it is the
species
that will be right, the species that will decide; for it will have
guided him
who observes it, and therefore, in following him whom it has guided, it
will
truly only be following its own unconscious, formless desires, which
will have
been expressed by him, and by him brought into light. Until such time as the species shall
discover the new
and needful experiment — and this it will quickly do when the danger
becomes
more acute; nay, for all we know, the expedient may have already been
found,
and, entirely unsuspected of us, be already transforming part of our
destinies
— until such time, while bound to act in external matters as though our
brothers’ salvation depended entirely on our exertions, it is open to
us, no
less than to the sages of old, to retire occasionally within ourselves.
We in
our turn shall perhaps find there “one of those things" of which the
contemplation shall suffice to bring us instantaneous enjoyment, if not
of the
perfect calm, at least of an indestructible hope. Though nature appear
unjust,
though nothing authorise us to declare that a superior power, or the
intellect
of the universe, rewards or punishes, here below or elsewhere, in
accordance
with the laws of our consciousness or with other laws that we shall
some day
admit; and finally, though between man and man, in other words, in our
relations with our fellows, our admirable desire for equity translate
itself
into a justice that is always incomplete, at the mercy of every error
of
reason, of every ambush laid by personal interest, and of all the evil
habits
of a social condition that still is sub-human, — it is none the less
certain
that an image of that invisible and incorruptible justice, which we
have vainly
sought in the sky or the universe, reposes in the depths of the moral
life of
every man. And though its method of action be such as to cause it to
pass
unperceived of most of our fellows, often indeed of our own
consciousness,
though all that it does be hidden and intangible, it is none the less
profoundly human and profoundly real. It would seem to hear, to
examine, all
that we say, and think, and strive for, in our exterior life; and if it
find a
little sincerity beneath, a little earnest desire for good, it will
transform
these into moral forces that shall extend and illumine our inner life,
and help
us to better thoughts, to better speech and endeavour, in the time to
come. It
will not add to, or take from, our wealth, it will bring no immunity
from
disease or from lightning, it will not prolong by one hour the life of
the
being we cherish; but if we have learned to reflect and to love: if, in
other
words, heart and brain have both done their duty, it will establish in
heart
and brain a contentment that, though perhaps stripped of illusion,
shall still
be inexhaustible and noble; it will confer a dignity of existence, an
intelligence, that shall suffice to sustain our life after the loss of
our
wealth, after the stroke of disease or lightning has fallen, after the
loved one
has forever quitted our arms. A good thought or deed brings a reward to
our
heart that it cannot, in the absence of a universal judge of nature,
extend to
the things around. It endeavours to create within us the happiness it
is unable
to produce in our material life. Denied all external outlet, it fills
our soul
the more. It prepares the space that soon shall be required by our
developing
intellect, our expanding peace and love. Helpless against the laws of
nature,
it is all-powerful over those that govern the happy equilibrium of
human
consciousness. And this is true of every stage of thought, of every
class of
action. A vast distance might seem to divide the labourer, who brings
up his
children honourably, lives his humble life and honourably does the work
that
falls to his lot, from the man who steadfastly perseveres in moral
heroism; but
each of these is acting and living, on the same plane as the other, and
the
same loyal, consoling region receives them both. And though it be
certain that
what we say and do must largely influence our material happiness, yet,
in
ultimate analysis, it is only by means of the spiritual organs that
even
material happiness can be fully and permanently enjoyed. Hence the
preponderating importance of thought. But of supreme importance, from
the point
of view of the reception we shall offer to the joys and sorrows of
life, is the
character, the frame of mind, the moral condition, that the things we
have
said, and done, and thought, will have created within us. Here there is
evidence
of admirable justice; and the intimate happiness that our moral being
derives
from the constant striving of the mind and heart for good becomes the
more
comprehensible when we realise that this happiness is only the surface
of the
goodly thought, or feeling, that is shining within our heart. Here may
we
indeed find that intelligent, moral bond between cause and effect that
we have
vainly sought in the external world; here, in moral matters, reigning
over the
good and evil that are warring in the depths of our consciousness, may
we in
truth discover a justice exactly similar to the one which we could
desire to
recognise in physical matters. But whence do we derive this desire if
not from
the justice within us; and is it not because this justice is so mighty
and
active in our heart that we are reluctant to believe in its
non-existence in
the universe? [36] We have spoken at great length of justice; but is it not the great mystery of man, the one that tends to take the place of most of the spiritual mysteries that govern his destiny? It has dethroned more than one god, more than one nameless power. It is the star evolved from the nebulous mass of our instincts and our incomprehensible life. It is not the solution of the enigma; and when, in the fulness of time, it shall become clearer to us, and shall truly reign all over the earth, there will come to us no greater knowledge of what we are, or why we are, whence we come or whither we go; but we shall at least have obeyed the first word of the enigma, and shall proceed, with a freer spirit and a more tranquil heart, to the search for its last secret. Finally, it comprises all the human virtues; and none but itself can offer the welcoming smile whereby these are ennobled and purified, none but itself can accord them the right to penetrate deep into our moral life. For every virtue must be maleficent and steeped in artifice that cannot support the fixed and eager regard of justice. And so do we find it at the heart of every ideal. It is at the centre of our love of truth, at the centre of our love of beauty. It is kindness and pity, it is generosity, heroism, love; for all these are the acts of justice of one who has risen sufficiently high to perceive that justice and injustice are not exclusively confined to what lies before him, to the narrow circle of obligations chance may have imposed, but that they stretch far beyond years, beyond neighbouring destinies, beyond what he regards as his duty, beyond what he loves; beyond what he seeks and encounters, beyond what he approves or respects, beyond his doubts and his fears, beyond the wrong-doing and even the crimes of the men, his brothers. |