Web
and Book design,
Copyright, Kellscraft Studio 1999-2017 (Return to Web Text-ures) |
(HOME)
|
II THE EVOLUTION OF MYSTERY [1] IT is not unreasonable to believe that I
the
paramount interest of life, all that is truly lofty and remarkable in
the
destiny of man, reposes almost entirely in the mystery that surrounds
us; in
the two mysteries, it may be, that are mightiest, most dreadful of all
—
fatality and death. And indeed there are many whom the fatigue induced
in their
minds by the natural uncertainties of science has almost compelled to
accept
this belief. I, too, believe, though in a somewhat different fashion,
that the
study of mystery in all its forms is the noblest to which the mind of
man can
devote itself; and truly it has ever been the study and care of those
who, in
science and art, in philosophy and literature, have refused to be
satisfied
merely to observe and portray the trivial, well-recognised truths,
facts, and
realities of life. And we find that the success of these men in their
endeavour, the depth of their insight into all that they knew, has most
strictly accorded with the respect in which they held all they did not
know,
with the dignity that their mind or imagination was able to confer on
the sum
of unknowable forces. Our consciousness of the unknown wherein we have
being
gives life a meaning and grandeur which must of necessity be absent if
we
persist in considering only the things that are known to us; if we too
readily
incline to believe that these must greatly transcend in importance the
things
which we know not yet. [2] It behoves every man to frame for himself
his own
general conception of the world. On this conception reposes his whole
human and
moral existence. But this general conception of the world, when closely
examined, is truly no more than a general conception of the unknown.
And we
must be careful; we have not the right, when ideas so vast confront us,
ideas
the results of which are so highly important, to select the one which
seems
most magnificent to us, most beautiful, or most attractive. The duty
lies on us
to choose the idea which seems truest, or rather, the only one which
seems
true; for I decline to believe that we can sincerely hesitate between
the truth
that is only apparent and the one that is real. The moment must always
come
when we feel that one of these two is possessed of more truth than the
other.
And to this truth we should cling: in our actions, our words, and our
thoughts;
in our art, in our science, in the life of our feelings and intellect.
Its
definition, perhaps, may elude us. It may possibly bring not one grain
of
reassuring conviction. Nay, essentially, perhaps, it may be but the
merest
impression, though profounder and more sincere than any previous
impression.
These things do not matter. It is not imperative that the truth we have
chosen
should be unimpeachable, or of absolute certainty. There is already
great gain
in our having been brought to experience that the truths we had loved
before
did not accord with reality, or with faithful experience of life; and
we have
every reason, therefore, to cherish our truth with heartiest gratitude
until
its own turn shall come to experience the fate it inflicted on its
predecessor.
The great mischief, the one which destroys our moral existence and
threatens
the integrity of our mind and our character, is not that we should
deceive
ourselves and love an uncertain truth, but that we should remain
constant to
one in which we no longer wholly believe. [3] If we sought nothing more than to invest
our
conception of the unknown with the utmost possible grandeur and
tragedy,
magnificence and might, there would be no need of such restrictions.
From many
points of view, doubtless, the most beautiful, most touching, most
religious
attitude in face of mystery is silence, and prayer, and fearful
acceptance.
When this immense, irresistible force confronts us — this inscrutable,
ceaselessly vigilant power, humanly superhuman, sovereignly
intelligent, and,
for all we know, even personal — must it not, at first sight, seem more
reverent, worthier, to offer complete submission, trying only to master
our
terror, than tranquilly to set on foot a patient, laborious
investigation? But
is the choice possible to us; have we still the right to choose? The
beauty or
dignity of the attitude we shall assume no longer is matter of moment.
It is
truth and sincerity that are called for to-day for the facing of all
things —
how much more when mystery confronts us! In the past, the prostration
of man,
his bending the knee, seemed beautiful because of what, in the past,
seemed
true. We have acquired no fresh certitude, perhaps; but for us, none
the less,
the truth of the past has ceased to be true. We have not bridged the
unknown;
but still, though we know not what it is, we do partially know what it
is not;
and it is before this we should bow were the attitude of our fathers to
be once
more assumed by us. For although it has not, perhaps, been
incontrovertibly
proved that the unknown is neither vigilant nor personal, neither
sovereignly
intelligent nor sovereignly just, or that it possesses none of the
passions,
intentions, virtues, or vices of man, it is still incomparably more
probable
that the unknown is entirely indifferent to all that appears of supreme
importance in this life of ours. It is incomparably more probable that
if, in
the vast and eternal scheme of the unknown, a minute and ephemeral
place be
reserved for man, his actions, be he the strongest or weakest, the best
or
worst of men, will be as unimportant there as the movements of the
obscurest
geological cell in the history of ocean or continent. Though it may not
have
been irrefutably shown that the infinite and invisible are not for ever
hovering round us, dealing out sorrow or joy in accordance with our
good or
evil intentions, guiding our destiny step by step, and preparing, with
the help
of innumerable forces, the incomprehensible but eternal law that
governs the
accidents of our birth, our future, our death, and our life beyond the
tomb, it
is still incomparably more probable that the invisible and infinite,
intervene
as they may at every moment in our life, enter therein only as
stupendous,
blind, indifferent elements; and that, though they pass over us, in us,
penetrate into our being, and inspire and mould our life, they are as
careless
of our individual existence as air, water, or light. And the whole of
our
conscious life, the life that forms our one certitude, that is our one
fixed
point in time and space, rests upon “incomparable probabilities" of
this
nature; but rarely are they as “incomparable" as these. [4] The hour when a lofty conviction forsakes
us should
never be one of regret. If a belief we have clung to goes, or a spring
snaps
within us; if we at last dethrone the idea that so long has held sway,
this is
proof of vitality, progress, of our marching steadily onwards, and
making good
use of all that lies to our hand. We should rejoice at the knowledge
that the
thought which so long has sustained us is proved incapable now of even
sustaining itself. And though we have nothing to put in the place of
the spring
that lies broken, there need still be no cause for sadness. Far better
the
place remain empty than that it be filled by a spring which the rust
corrodes,
or by a new truth in which we do not wholly believe. And besides, the
place is
not really empty. Determinate truth may have not yet arrived, but
still, in its
own deep recess, there hides a truth without name, which waits and
calls. And
if it wait and call too long in the void, and nothing arise in the
place of the
vanished spring, it still shall be found that, in moral no less than in
physical life, necessity will be able to create the organ it needs, and
that
the negative truth will at last find sufficient force in itself to set
the idle
machinery going. And the lives that possess no more than one force of
this kind
are not the least strenuous, the least ardent, or the least useful. And even though our belief forsake us
entirely, it
still will take with it nothing of what we have given, nor will there
be lost
one single sincere, religious, disinterested effort that we have put
forth to
ennoble this faith, to exalt or embellish it. Every thought we have
added, each
worthy sacrifice we have had the courage to make in its name, will have
left
its indelible mark on our moral existence. The body is gone, but the
palace it
built still stands, and the space it has conquered will remain forever
unenclosed. It is our duty, and one we dare not renounce, to prepare
homes for
truths that shall come, to maintain in good order the forces destined
to serve
them, and to create open spaces within us; nor can the time thus
employed be
possibly wasted. [5] These thoughts have arisen within me
through my
having been compelled, a few days ago, to glance over two or three
little
dramas of mine, wherein lies revealed the disquiet of a mind that has
given
itself wholly to mystery, — a disquiet legitimate enough in itself,
perhaps,
but not so inevitable as to warrant its own complacency. The keynote of
these
little plays is dread of the unknown that surrounds us. I, or rather
some
obscure poetical feeling within me (for with the sincerest of poets a
division
must often be made between the instinctive feeling of their art and the
thoughts
of their real life) seemed to believe in a species of monstrous,
invisible,
fatal power that gave heed to our every action, and was hostile to our
smile,
to our life, to our peace and our love. Its intentions could not be
divined,
but the spirit of the drama assumed them to be malevolent always. In
its
essence, perhaps, this power was just, but only in anger; and it
exercised
justice in a manner so crooked, so secret, so sluggish and remote, that
its
punishments — for it never rewarded — took the semblance of
inexplicable,
arbitrary acts of fate. We had there, in a word, more or less the idea
of the
God of the Christians, blent with that of ancient fatality, lurking in
nature’s
impenetrable twilight, whence it eagerly watched, contested, and
saddened the
projects, the feelings, the thoughts, and the happiness of man. [6] This unknown would most frequently appear
in the
shape of death. The presence of death — infinite, menacing, for ever
treacherously active — filled every interstice of the poem. The problem
of
existence was answered only by the enigma of annihilation. And it was a
callous, inexorable death; blind, and groping its mysterious way with
only
chance to guide it; laying its hands preferentially on the youngest and
the
least unhappy, since these held themselves less motionless than others,
and
that every too sudden movement in the night arrested its attention. And
around
it were only poor little trembling, elementary creatures, who shivered
for an
instant and wept, on the brink of a gulf; and their words and their
tears had
importance only from the fact that each word they spoke and each tear
they shed
fell into this gulf, and were at times so strangely resonant there as
to lead
one to think that the gulf must be vast if tear or word, as it fell,
could send
forth so confused and muffled a sound. [7] Such a conception of life is not healthy,
whatever
show of reason it may seem to possess; and I would not allude to it
here were
it not for the fact that we find this idea, or one closely akin to it,
governing the hearts of most men, however tranquil, or thoughtful, or
earnest
they may be, at the approach of the slightest misfortune. There is
evidently a
side to our nature which, notwithstanding all we may learn and master,
and the
certitudes we may acquire, destines us never to be other than poor,
weak,
useless creatures, consecrated to death, and playthings of the vast and
heedless forces that surround us. We appear for an instant in limitless
space,
our one appreciable mission the propagation of a species that itself
has no
appreciable mission in the scheme of a universe whose extent and
duration
baffle the most daring, most powerful brain. This is a truth; it is one
of
those profound but sterile truths which the poet may salute as he
passes on his
way; but it is a truth in the neighbourhood of which the man with the
thousand
duties who lives in the poet will do well not to abide too long. And of
truths
such as this there are many that are lofty and deserving of all our
respect,
but in their domain it were unwise to lay ourselves down and sleep. So
many
truths environ us that it may safely be said that few men can be found,
of the
wickedest, even, who have not for counsel and guide a grave and
respectable
truth. Yes, it is a truth — the vastest, most certain of truths, if one
will —
that our life is nothing, and our efforts the merest jest; our
existence, that
of our planet, only a miserable accident in the history of worlds; but
it is no
less a truth that, to us, our life and our planet are the most
important, nay,
the only important phenomena in the history of worlds. And of these
truths
which is the truer? Does the first of necessity destroy the second?
Without the
second, should we have had the courage to formulate the first? The one
appeals
to our imagination, and may be helpful to it in its own domain; but the
other
directly interests our actual life. It is well that each have its
share. The
truth that is undoubtedly truest from the human point of view must
evidently
appeal to us more than the truth which is truest from the universal
point of
view. Ignorant as we are of the aim of the universe, how shall we tell
whether
or no it concern itself with the interests of our race? The probable
futility
of our life and our species is a truth which regards us indirectly
only, and
may well, therefore, be left in suspense. The other truth, that
indicates
clearly the importance of life, may perhaps be a more restricted one,
but it
has a direct, incontestable, actual bearing upon ourselves. To
sacrifice or even
subordinate it to an alien truth must surely be wrong. The first truth
should
never be lost sight of; it will strengthen and illumine the second,
whose
government will thus become more intelligent and benign; the first
truth will
teach us to profit by all that the second does not include. And if we
allow it
to sadden our heart or arrest our action, we have not sufficiently
realised
that the vast but precarious space it fills in the region of important
truths
is governed by countless problems which as yet are unsolved; while the
problems
whereon the second truth rests are daily resolved by real life. The
first truth
is still in the dangerous, feverish stage through which all truths must
pass
before they can penetrate freely into our heart and our brain, — a
stage of
jealousy, truculence, which renders the neighbourhood of another truth
insupportable to them. We must wait till the fever subsides; and if the
home
that we have prepared in our spirit be sufficiently spacious and pure,
we shall
find very soon that the most contradictory truths will be conscious
only of the
mysterious bond that unites them, and will silently join with each
other to
place in the front rank of all, and there help and sustain, that truth
from
among them which calmly went on with its work while the others were
fretfully
jangling, — that truth which can do the most good, and brings with it
the
uttermost hope. [8] The strangest feature of the present time
is the
confusion which reigns in our instincts and feelings — in our ideas,
too, save
at our most lucid, most tranquil, most thoughtful moments — on the
subject of
the intervention of the unknown or mysterious in the truly grave events
of
life. We find, amidst this confusion, feelings which no longer accord
with any
precise, living, accepted idea; such, for instance, as concern the
existence of
a determinate God, conceived as more or less anthropomorphic,
providential,
personal, and unceasingly vigilant. We find feelings which, as yet, are
only
partially ideas; as those which deal with fatality, destiny, the
justice of
things. We find ideas which will soon turn to feelings; those that
treat of the
law of the species, evolution, selection, the will-power of the race,
etc. And
finally we discover ideas which still are purely ideas, too uncertain
and
scattered for us to be able to predict at what moment they will turn
into
feelings, and thus materially influence our actions, our acceptance of
life,
our joys and our sorrows. [9] If in actual life this confusion is not so
apparent,
it is only because actual life will but rarely express itself, or
condescend to
make use of image or formula to relate its experience. This state of
mind,
however, is clearly discernible in all those whose self-imposed mission
it is
to depict real life, to explain and interpret it, and throw light on
the hidden
causes of good and evil destiny. It is of the poets I speak, of
dramatic poets
above all, who are occupied with external and active life; and it
matters not
whether they produce novels, tragedies, the drama properly so called,
or
historical studies, for I give to the words “poets" and “dramatic
poets" their widest significance. It cannot be denied that the possession of
a dominant
idea, one that may be said to exclude all others, must confer
considerable
power on the poet, or “interpreter of life;” and in the degree that the
idea is
mysterious, and difficult of definition or control, will be the extent
of this
power and its conspicuousness in the poem. And this is entirely
legitimate, so
long as the poet himself has not the least doubt as to the value of his
idea;
and there are many admirable poets who have never hesitated, paused, or
doubted. Thus it is that we find the idea of heroic duty filling so
enormous a
space in the tragedies of Corneille, that of absolute faith in the
dramas of
Calderon, that of the tyranny of destiny in the works of Sophocles. [10] Of these three ideas, that of heroic duty
is the most
human and the least mysterious; and although far more restricted to-day
than at
the time of Corneille, — for there are few such duties which it would
not now
be reasonable, and even heroic, perhaps, to call into question, and it
becomes
ever more and more difficult to find one that is truly heroic, —
conditions may
still be imagined under which recourse thereto may be legitimate in the
poet. But will he discover in faith — to-day no
more than a
shadowy memory to the most fervent believer — that inspiration and
strength by
whose aid Corneille was able to depict the God of the Christians as the
august,
omnipresent actor of his dramas, invisible but untiringly active, and
sovereign
always? Or is it possible still for a reasonable being, whose eyes rest
calmly
on the life about him, to believe in the tyranny of fate; of that
sluggish,
unswerving, preordained, inscrutable force which urges a given man, or
family,
by given ways to a given disaster or death? For though it be true that
our life
is subject to many an unknown force, we at least are aware that these
forces
would seem to be blind, indifferent, unconscious, and that their most
insidious
attacks may be in some measure averted by the wisest among us. Can we
still be
allowed, then, to believe that the universe holds a power so idle, so
wretched,
as to concern itself solely in saddening, frustrating, and terrifying
the
projects and schemes of man? Immanent justice is another mysterious and
sovereign
force, whereof use has been made; but it is only the feeblest of
writers who
have ventured to accept this postulate in its entirety, — only those to
whom
reality and probability were matters of smallest moment. The
affirmation that
wickedness is necessarily and visibly punished in this life, and virtue
as
necessarily and visibly rewarded, is too manifestly opposed to the most
elementary daily experience, too wildly inconsistent a dream, for the
true poet
ever to accept it as the basis of his drama. And, on the other hand, if
we
refer to a future life the bestowal of reward and punishment, we are
merely
entering by another gate the region of divine justice. For, indeed,
unless
immanent justice be infallible, permanent, unvarying, and inevitable,
it
becomes no more than a curious, well-meaning caprice of fate; and from
that
moment it no longer is justice, or even fate; it shrinks into merest
chance —
in other words, almost into nothingness. There is, it is true, a very real immanent
justice; I
refer to the force which enacts that the vicious, malevolent, cruel,
disloyal
man shall be morally less happy than he who is honest and good,
affectionate,
gentle, and just. But here it is inward justice whose workings we see;
a very
human, natural, comprehensible force, the study of whose cause and
effect must
of necessity lead to psychological drama, where there no longer is need
of the
vast and mysterious background which lent its solemn and awful
perspective to
the events of history and legend. But is it legitimate deliberately to
misconceive the unknown that governs our life in order that we may
reconstruct
this mysterious background? [11] While on this subject of dominant and
mysterious
ideas, we shall do well to consider the forms that the idea of fatality
has
taken and for ever is taking; for fatality even to-day still provides
the
supreme explanation for all that we cannot explain; and it is to
fatality still
that the thoughts of the “interpreter of life" unceasingly turn. The poets have endeavoured to transform
it, to make
it attractive, to restore its youth. They have contrived, in their
works, a
hundred new and winding canals through which to introduce the icy
waters of the
great and desolate river whose banks have been gradually shunned by the
dwellings of men. And of those most successful in making us share the
illusion
that they were conferring a solemn, definitive meaning on life, there
are few
who have not instinctively recognised the sovereign importance
conferred on the
actions of men by the irresponsible power of an ever august and
unerring
destiny. Fatality would seem to be the pre-eminent tragical force; it
no sooner
appears in a drama than it does of itself three-fourths of all that
needs
doing. It may safely be said that the poet who could find to-day, in
material
science, in the unknown that surrounds us, or in his own heart, the
equivalent
for ancient fatality — a force, that is, of equally irresistible
predestination, a force as universally admitted — would infallibly
produce a
masterpiece. It is true, however, that he would have, at the same time,
to
solve the mighty enigma for whose word we are all of us seeking; so
that this
supposition is not likely to be realised very soon. [12] This is the source, then, whence the
lustral water is
drawn with which the poets have purified the cruellest of tragedies.
There is
an instinct in man that worships fatality, and he is apt to regard
whatever
pertains thereto as incontestable, solemn, and beautiful. His cry is
for
freedom; but circumstances arise when he rather would tell himself that
he is
not free. The unbending, malignant goddess is more acceptable often
than the
divinity who only asks for an effort that shall avert disaster. All
things
notwithstanding, it pleases us still to be ruled by a power that
nothing can
turn from its purpose; and whatever our mental dignity may lose by such
a
belief is gained by a kind of sentimental vanity in us, which
complacently
dwells on the measureless force that for ever keeps watch on our plans,
and
confers on our simplest action a mysterious, eternal significance.
Fatality,
briefly, explains and excuses all things, by relegating to a sufficient
distance in the invisible or the unintelligible all that it would be
hard to
explain and more difficult still to excuse. [13] Therefore it is that so many have turned
to the
dismembered statue of the terrible goddess who reigned in the dramas of
Euripides,
Sophocles, and Æschylus, and that the scattered fragments of her limbs
have
provided more than one poet with the marble required for the fashioning
of a
newer divinity, who should be more human, less arbitrary, and less
inconceivable than she of old. The fatality of the passions, for
instance, has
thus been evolved. But for a passion truly to be fatal in a soul aware
of
itself, for the mystery to reappear that shall make crime pardonable by
investing it with loftiness and lifting it high above the will of man,
— for
these we require the intervention of a God, or some other equally
irresistible,
infinite force. Wagner, therefore, in Tristram and Iseult, makes use of
the
philtre, as Shakespeare of the witches in Macbeth, Racine of the oracle
of
Calchas in Iphigenia, and of Venus’ hatred in Phèdre. We have travelled
in a
circle, and find ourselves back once more at the very heart of the
craving of
former days. This expedient may be more or less legitimate in archaic
or
legendary drama, where there is room for all kinds of poetic fantasy;
but in
the drama which pretends to actual truth we demand another
intervention, one
that shall seem to us more genuinely irresistible, if crimes like
Macbeth’s,
such a deed of horror as that to which Agamemnon consented: perhaps,
too, the
kind of love that burned in Phèdre, shall achieve their mysterious
excuse, and
acquire a grandeur and sombre nobility that intrinsically they do not
possess.
Take away from Macbeth the fatal predestination, the intervention of
Hell, the
heroic struggle with an occult justice that for ever is revealing
itself
through a thousand fissures of revolting nature, and Macbeth is merely
a
frantic, contemptible murderer. Take away the oracle of Calchas, and
Agamemnon
becomes abominable. Take away the hatred of Venus, and what is Phèdre
but a
neurotic creature, whose "moral quality" and power of resistance to
evil are too pronouncedly feeble for our intellect to take any genuine
interest
in the calamity that befalls her? [14] Truly, these supernatural interventions
to-day
satisfy neither spectator nor reader. Though he know it not, perhaps,
and
strive as he may, it is no longer possible for him to regard them
seriously in
the depths of his consciousness. His conception of the universe is
other. He no
longer detects the working of a narrow, determined, obstinate, violent
will in
the multitude of forces that strive in him and about him. He knows that
the
criminal whom he may meet in actual life has been urged into crime by
misfortune, education, atavism, or by movements of passion which he has
himself
experienced and subdued, while recognising that there might have been
circumstances under which their repression would have been a matter of
exceeding difficulty. He will not, it is true, always be able to
discover the
cause of these misfortunes, or of these movements of passion; and his
endeavour
to account for the injustice of education or heredity will probably be
no less
unsuccessful. But for all that he will no longer incline to attribute a
particular crime to the wrath of a God, the direct intervention of
Hell, or to
a series of changeless decrees inscribed in the book of fate. Why ask
of him,
then, to accept in a poem an explanation which he refuses in life? Is
the
poet’s duty not rather to furnish an explanation loftier, clearer, more
widely
and profoundly human, than any his reader can find for himself? For,
indeed,
this wrath of the gods, intervention of Hell, and writing in letters of
fire,
are to him no more to-day than so many symbols that have long ceased to
content
him. It is time that the poet should realise that the symbol is
legitimate only
when it stands for accepted truth, or for truth which as yet we cannot,
or will
not, accept; but the symbol is out of place at a time when it is truth
itself
that we seek. And besides, to merit admission into a really living
poem, the
symbol should be at least as great and beautiful as the truth for which
it
stands, and should, moreover, precede this truth, and not follow a long
way
behind. [15] We see, therefore, how surpassingly
difficult it must
have become to introduce great crimes, or cruel, unbridled, tragical
passions
into a modern work,’ above all if that work be destined for stage
presentation;
for the poet will seek in vain for the mysterious excuse these crimes
or
passions demand. And yet, for all that, so deeply is this craving for
mysterious excuse implanted within us, so satisfied are we that man is,
at
bottom, never as guilty as he may appear, that we are still fully
content, when
considering passions or crimes of this nature, to admit some kind of
fatal
intervention that at least may not seem too manifestly unacceptable. This excuse, however, will be sought by us
only when
the persons guilty of crimes which are contrary to human nature, then
the
victims of misfortunes which they could not foresee, which seem
undeserved to
us, inexplicable, wholly abnormal, are more or less superior beings,
possessed
of their fullest share of consciousness. We are loath to admit that an
extraordinary crime or disaster can have a purely human cause. In spite
of all,
we persistently seek in some way to explain the inexplicable. We should
not be
satisfied if the poet were simply to say to us: “You see here the wrong
that
was done by this strong, this conscious, intelligent man. Behold the
misfortune
this hero encountered; this good man’s ruin and sorrow. See, too, how
this sage
is crushed by tragic, irremediable wickedness. The human causes of
these events
are evident to you. I have no other explanation to offer, unless it be
perhaps
the indifference of the universe towards the actions of man.” Our
dissatisfaction would vanish if he could succeed in conveying to us the
sensation of this indifference, if he could show it in action; but, as
it is
the property of indifference never to interfere or act, that would seem
to be
more or less unachievable. [16] But when we turn to the by no means
inevitable
jealousy of Othello, or to the misfortunes of Romeo and Juliet, which
were
surely not preordained, we discover no need of explanation, or of the
purifying
influence of fatality. In another drama, Ford’s masterpiece, ‘Tis Pity
She’s a
Whore, which revolves around the incestuous love of Giovanni for his
sister
Annabella, we are compelled either to turn away in horror, or to seek
the
mysterious excuse in its habitual haunt on the shore of the gulf. But
even
here, the first painful shock over, we find it is not imperative. For
the love
of brother for sister, viewed from a standpoint sufficiently lofty, is
a crime
against morality, but not against human nature; and there is at least
some
measure of palliation in the youth of the pair, and in the passion that
blinds
them. Othello, too, the semi-barbarian who does Desdemona to death, has
been
goaded to madness by the machinations of Iago; and even this last can
plead his
by no means gratuitous hatred. The disasters that weighed so heavily on
the
lovers of Verona were due to the inexperience of the victims, to the
manifest
disproportion between their strength and that of their enemies; and
although we
may pity the man who succumbs to superior human force, his downfall
does not
surprise us. We are not impelled to seek explanation elsewhere, to ask
questions of fate; and unless he appear to fall victim to superhuman
injustice
we are content to tell ourselves that what has happened was bound to
happen. It
is only when disaster occurs after every precaution is taken that we
could
ourselves have devised, that we become conscious of the need for other
explanation. [17] We find it difficult, therefore, to
conceive or admit
as naturally, humanly possible that a crime shall be committed by a
person who
apparently is endowed with fullest intelligence and consciousness; or
that
misfortune should befall him which seems in its essence to be
inexplicable,
undeserved, and unexpected. It follows, therefore, that the poet can
only place
on the stage (this phrase I use merely as an abbreviation: it would be
more
correct to say, “cause us to assist at some adventure whereof we know
personally neither the actors nor the totality of the circumstances")
faults, crimes, and acts of injustice committed by persons of defective
consciousness, as also disasters befalling feeble beings unable to
control
their desires — innocent creatures, it may be, but thick-sighted,
imprudent,
and reckless. Under these conditions there would seem to be no call for
the
intervention of anything beyond the limit of normal human psychology.
But such
a conception of the theatre would be at absolute variance with real
life, where
we find crimes committed by persons of fullest consciousness, and the
most
inexplicable, inconceivable, unmerited misfortunes befalling the
wisest, the
best, most virtuous and prudent of men. Dramas which deal with
unconscious
creatures, whom their own feebleness oppresses and their own desires
overcome,
excite our interest, and arouse our pity; but the veritable drama, the
one
which probes to the heart of things and grapples with important truths,
— our
own personal drama, in a word, which forever hangs over our life, — is
the one
wherein the strong, intelligent, and conscious commit errors, faults,
and
crimes which are almost inevitable; wherein the wise and upright
struggle with
all-powerful calamity, with forces destructive to wisdom and virtue;
for it is
worthy of note that the spectator, however feeble, dishonest even, he
may be in
real life, still enrols himself always among the virtuous, just, and
strong;
and when he reflects on the misfortunes of the weak, or even witnesses
them, he
resolutely declines to imagine himself in the place of the victims. [18] Here we attain the limit of the human
will, the
gloomy boundary-line of the influence that the most just and
enlightened of men
is able to exert on events that decide his future happiness or sorrow.
No great
drama exists, or poem of lofty aim, but one of its heroes shall stray
to this
frontier where his destiny waits for the seal. Why has this wise, this
virtuous
man committed this fault or this crime? Why has that woman, who knows
so well
the meaning of all that she does, hazarded the gesture which must so
inevitably
summon everlasting sorrow? By whom have the links been forged of the
chain of
disaster whose fetters have crushed this innocent family? Why do all
things
crumble around one, and fall into ruins, while the other, his
neighbour, less
active and strong, less skilful and wise, find ever material by him to
build up
his life anew? Why do tenderness, beauty, and love flock to the path of
some,
where others meet hatred only, and malice, and treachery? Why
persistent
happiness here, and yonder, though merits be equal, nought but
unceasing
disaster? Why is this house for ever beset with the storm, while over
that
other shines the peace of unvarying stars? Why genius, and riches, and
health
on this side, and yonder disease, imbecility, poverty? Whence has the
passion
been sent that has wrought such terrible grief, and whence the passion
that
proved the source of such wonderful joy? Why does the youth whom
yesterday I
met go on his tranquil road to profoundest happiness, while his friend,
with
the same methodical, peaceful, ignorant step, proceeds on his way to
death? [19] Life will often place these problems
before us; but
how rarely are we compelled to refer their solution to the
supernatural,
mysterious, superhuman, or preordained! It is only the fervent believer
who
will still be content to see there the finger of divine intervention.
Such of
us, however, as have entered the house where the storm has raged, as
well as
the house of peace, have rarely issued from them without most clearly
detecting
the essentially human reasons of both peace and storm. We who have
known the
wise and upright man who has been guilty of error or crime, are
acquainted also
with the circumstances also which induced his action, and these
circumstances
seem to us in no way supernatural. As we draw near to the woman whose
gesture
brought misery to her, we learn very soon that this gesture might have
been
avoided, and that, in her place, we should have refrained. The friends
of the
man around whom all fell into ruins, and of the neighbour who ever was
able to
build up his life anew, will have observed before that the acorn
sometimes will
fall on to rock, and sometimes on fertile soil. And though poverty,
sickness and
death remain still the three inequitable goddesses of human existence,
they no
longer awake in us the superstitious fears of bygone days. We regard
them
to-day as essentially indifferent, unconscious, blind. We know that
they
recognise none of the ideal laws which we once believed that they
sanctioned;
and it only too often has happened that, at the very moment we were
whispering
to ourselves of “purification, trial, reward, punishment,” their
undiscerning
caprice gave the lie to the too lofty, too moral title which we were
about to
bestow. [20] Our imagination, it is true, is inclined
to admit,
perhaps to desire, the intervention of the superhuman; but, for all
that, there
are few, even among the most mystic, who are not convinced that our
moral misfortunes
are, in their essence, determined by our mind and our character; and
similarly,
that our physical misfortunes are due in part to the workings of
certain forces
which often are misunderstood, and in part to the generally ill-defined
relation of cause to effect; nor is it unreasonable to hope that light
may be
thrown on these problems as we penetrate further into the secrets of
nature. We
have here a certitude upon which our whole life depends; a certitude
which is
shaken only when we consider our own misfortunes, for then we shrink
from
analysing or admitting the faults we ourselves have committed. There is
a
hopefulness in man which renders him unwilling to grant that the cause
of his
misfortune may be as transparent as that of the wave which dies away in
the
sand or is hurled on the cliff, of the insect whose little wings gleam
for an
instant in the light of the sun till the passing bird absorbs its
existence. [21] Let me suppose that a neighbour of mine,
whom I know
very intimately, whose regular habits and inoffensive manners have won
my
esteem, should successively lose his wife in a railway accident, one
son at
sea, another in a fire, the third and last by disease. I should, of
course, be
painfully shocked and grieved; but still it would not occur to me to
attribute
this series of disasters to a divine vengeance or an invisible justice,
to a
strange, ill-starred predestination, or an active, persistent,
inevitable
fatality. My thoughts would fly to the myriad unfortunate hazards of
life; I
should be appalled at the frightful coincidence of calamity; but in me
there
would be no suggestion of a superhuman will that had hurled the train
over the
precipice, steered the ship on to rocks, or kindled the flames; I
should hold
it incredible that such monstrous efforts could have been put forth
with the
sole object of inflicting punishment and despair upon a poor wretch,
because of
some error he might have committed — one of those grave human errors
which yet
are so petty in face of the universe; an error which perhaps had not
issued
from either his heart or his brain, and had stirred not one blade of
grass on
the earth’s whole surface. [22] But he, this neighbour of mine, on whom
these
terrible blows have successively fallen like so many lightning-flashes
on a
black night of storm — will he think as I do, will these catastrophes
seem
natural to him, and ordinary, and susceptible of explanation? Will not
the
words destiny, fortune, hazard, ill-luck, fatality, star — the word
Providence,
perhaps — assume in his mind a significance they never have assumed
before?
Will not the light beneath which he questions his consciousness be a
different
light from my own; will he not feel round his life an influence, a
power, a
kind of evil intention, that are imperceptible to me? And who is right,
he or
I? Which of us two sees more clearly, and further? Do truths that in
calmer
times lie hidden float to the surface in hours of trouble; and which is
the
moment we should choose to establish the meaning of life? The “interpreter of life,” as a rule,
selects the
troubled hours. He places himself, and us, in the soul-state of his
victims. He
shows their misfortunes to us in perspective; and so sharply,
concretely, that
we have for the moment the illusion of a personal disaster. And,
indeed, it is
more or less impossible for him to depict them as they would occur in
real
life. If we had spent long years with the hero of the drama which has
stirred
us so painfully, had he been our brother, our father, our friend, we
should
probably have noted, recognised, counted one by one as they passed, all
the
causes of his misfortune, which then would not only appear less
extraordinary
to us, but perfectly natural even, and humanly almost inevitable. But
to the
“interpreter of life" is given neither power nor occasion to acquaint
us
with each veritable cause. For these causes, as a rule, are infinitely
slow in
their movement, and countless in number, and slight, and of small
apparent
significance. He is therefore led to adopt a general cause, one
sufficiently
vast to embrace the whole drama, in place of the real and human causes
which he
is unable to show us, unable, too, himself to examine and study. And
where
shall a general cause of sufficient vastness be found, if not in the
two or
three words we breathe to ourselves when silence oppresses us: words
like
fatality, divinity, Providence, or obscure and nameless justice? [23] The question before us now is how far this
procedure
can be beneficial, or even legitimate; as also whether it be the
mission of the
poet to present, and insist on, the distress and confusion of our least
lucid
hours, or to add to the clearsightedness of the moments when we
conceive
ourselves to enjoy the fullest possession of our force and our reason.
In our
own misfortunes there is something of good, and something of good must
therefore be found in the illusion of personal misfortune. We are made
to look
into ourselves; our errors, our weaknesses, are more clearly revealed;
it is
shown to us where we have strayed. There falls a light on our
consciousness a
thousand times more searching, more active, than could spring from many
arduous
years of meditation and study. We are forced to emerge from ourselves,
and to
let our eyes rest on those round about us; we are rendered more keenly
alive to
the sorrows of others. There are some who will tell us that misfortune
does
even more, — that it urges our glance on high, and compels us to bow to
a power
superior to our own, to an unseen justice, to an impenetrable, infinite
mystery. Can this indeed be the best of all possible issues? Ah, yes,
it was
well, from the standpoint of religious morality, that misfortune should
teach
us to lift up our eyes and look on an eternal, unchanging, undeniable
God,
sovereignly beautiful, sovereignly just, and sovereignly good. It was
well that
the poet who found in his God an unquestionable ideal should
incessantly hold
before us this unique, this definitive ideal. But to-day, if we look
away from
the truth, from the ordinary experience of life, on what shall our
eager glance
rest? If we discard the more or less compensatory laws of conscience
and inward
happiness, what shall we say when triumphant injustice confronts us, or
successful, unpunished crime? How shall we account for the death of a
child, the
miserable end of an innocent man, or the disaster hurled by cruel fate
on some
unfortunate creature, if we seek explanations loftier, more definite,
more
comprehensive and decisive than those that are found satisfactory in
every-day
life, for the reason that they are the only ones that accord with a
certain
number of realities? Is it right that the poet, in his eager desire to
contrive
a solemn atmosphere for his drama, should arouse from their slumber
sentiments,
errors, prejudices, and fears, which we would attack and rebuke were we
to
discover them in the hearts of our friends or our children? Man has at
last,
through his study of the habits of spirit and brain, of the laws of
existence,
the caprices of fate, and the maternal indifference of nature — man has
at
last, and laboriously, acquired some few certitudes, that are worthy of
all
respect; and is the poet entitled to seize on the moment of anguish in
order to
oust all these certitudes, and set up in their place a fatality to
which every
action of ours gives the lie, or powers before which we would refuse to
kneel
did the blow fall on us that has prostrated his hero; or a mystic
justice that,
for all it may sweep away the need for many an embarrassing
explanation, bears
yet not the slightest kinship to the active and personal justice we all
of us
recognise in our own personal life? [24] And yet this is what the “interpreter of
life"
will more or less deliberately do from the moment he seeks to invest
his work
with a lofty spirit, with a deep and religious beauty, with the sense
of the
infinite. Even though this work of his may be of the sincerest, though
it
express as nearly as may be his own most intimate truth, he believes
that this
truth is enhanced, and established more firmly, by being surrounded
with
phantoms of a forgotten past. Might not the symbols he needs, the
hypotheses,
images, the touchstone for all that cannot be explained, be less
frequently
sought in that which he knows is not true, and more often in that which
will
one day be a truth? Does the unearthing of bygone terrors, or the
borrowing of
light from a Hell that has ceased to be, make death more sublime? Does
dependence on a supreme but imaginary will ennoble our destiny? Does
justice —
that vast network woven by human action and reaction over the
unchanging wisdom
of nature’s moral and physical forces — does justice become more
majestic
through being lodged in the hands of a unique judge, whom the very
spirit of
the drama dethrones and destroys? [25] Let us ask ourselves whether the hour may
not have
come for the earnest revision of the symbols, the images, sentiments,
beauty,
wherewith we still seek to glorify in us the spectacle of the world. This beauty, these feelings and
sentiments, to-day
unquestionably bear only the most distant relation to the phenomena,
thoughts,
nay even the dreams, of our actual existence; and if they are suffered
still to
abide with us, it is rather as tender and innocent memories of a past
that was
more credulous, and nearer to the childhood of man. Were it not well,
then,
that those whose mission it is to make more evident to us the beauty
and
harmony of the world we live in, should march ever onwards and let
their steps
tend to the actual truth of this world? Their conception of the
universe need
not be stripped of a single one of the ornaments wherewith they
embellish it;
but why seek these ornaments so often among mere recollections, however
smiling
or terrible, and so seldom from among the essential thoughts which have
helped
them to build, and effectively organise, their spiritual and sentient
life? It can never be right to dwell in the midst of false images, even though these are known to be false. The time will come when the illusory image will usurp the place of the just idea it has seemed to represent. We shall not reduce the part of the infinite and the mysterious by employing other images, by framing other and juster conceptions. Do what we may, this part can never be lessened. It will always be found deep down in the heart of men, at the root of each problem, pervading the universe. And for all that the substance, the place of these mysteries, may seem to have changed, their extent and power remain for ever the same. Has not — to take but one instance — has not the phenomenon of the existence, everywhere among us, of a kind of supreme and wholly spiritual justice, unarmed, unadorned, unequipped, moving slowly but never swerving, remaining stable and changeless in a world where injustice would seem to reign — has this phenomenon not cause and effect as deep, as exhaustless — is it not as astounding, as admirable — as the wisdom of an eternal and omnipresent Judge? Should this Judge be held more convincing for that he is less conceivable? Are fewer sources of beauty, or occasions for genius to exercise insight and power, to be found in what can be explained than in what is, a priori, inexplicable? Does not, for instance, a victorious but unjust war (such as those of the Romans, of England today, the conquests of Spain in America, etc.) in the end always demoralise the victor and thrust upon him errors, faults, and habits whereby he is made to pay dearly for his triumph; and is not the minute, the relentless labour of this psychological justice as absorbing, as vast, as the intervention of a superhuman justice? And may not the same be said of the justice that lives in each one of us, that causes the space left for peace, inner happiness, love, to expand or contract in our mind and our heart in conformity with our striving towards that which is just or unjust? [26] And to turn to one mystery more, the most
awful of
all, that of death — would anyone pretend that our perception of
justice, of
goodness and beauty, or our intellectual, sentient power, our eagerness
for all
that draws near to the infinite, all-powerful, eternal, has dwindled
since
death has finally ceased to be held the immense and exclusive anguish
of life?
Does not each new generation find the burden lighter to bear as the
forms of
death grow less violent and its posthumous terrors fade? It is the
illness that
goes before, the physical pain, of which we are to-day most afraid. But
death
is no longer the hour of the wrathful, inscrutable judge; no longer the
one and
the terrible goal, the gulf of misery and eternal punishment. It is
slowly becoming
— indeed, in some cases, it has already become — the wished-for repose
of a
life that draws to its end. Its weight no longer oppresses each one of
our
actions; and, above all — for this is the most striking change — it has
ceased
to intrude itself into our morality. And is this morality of ours less
lofty,
less pure, less profound, because of the disinterestedness it has thus
acquired? Has the loss of an overwhelming dread robbed mankind of a
single
precious, indispensable feeling? And must not life itself find gain in
the
importance wrested from death? Surely; for the neutral. forces that we
hold in
reserve within us are waiting and ready; and every discouragement,
sorrow, or
fear that departs has its place quickly filled by a certitude,
admiration, or
hope.
The poet is inclined to personify fatality
and
justice, and give outward form to forces really within us, for the
reason that
to show them at work in ourselves is a matter of exceeding difficulty;
and
further, that the unknown and the infinite, to the extent that they are
unknown
and infinite, i. e., lacking personality, intelligence, and morality,
are
powerless to move us. And here it is curious to note that we are in no
degree
affected by material mystery, however dangerous or obscure, or by
psychological
justice, however involved its results. It is not the incomprehensible
in nature
that masters and crushes us, but the thought that nature may possibly
be
governed by a conscious, superior, reasoning will: one that, although
superhuman, has yet some kinship to the will of man. What we dread, in
a word,
is the presence of a God; and speak as we may of fatality, justice, or
mystery,
it is always God whom we fear: a being, that is, like ourselves, though
almighty, eternal, invisible, and infinite. A moral force that was not
conceived in the image of man would most likely inspire no fear. It is
not the
unknown in nature that fills us with dread; it is not the mystery of
the world
we live in. It is the mystery of another world from which we recoil; it
is the
moral, and not the material, enigma. There is nothing, for instance,
more
obscure than the combination of causes which produce the earthquake,
that most
terrible of all catastrophes. But the earthquake, though it alarm our
body,
will bring no fear to our mind unless we regard it as an act of
justice, of
mysterious vengeance, of supernatural punishment. And so it is, too,
with the
thunderstorm, with illness, with death, with the myriad phenomena and
accidents
of life. It would seem as though the true alarm of our soul, the great
fear
which stirs other instincts within us than that of mere
self-preservation, is
only called forth by the thought of a more or less determinate God, of
a
mysterious consciousness, a permanent, invisible justice, or a
vigilant,
eternal Providence. But does the “interpreter of life,” who succeeds in
arousing this fear, bring us thereby nearer to truth, and is it his
mission to
convey to us sorrow, and trouble, and painful emotion, or peace,
satisfaction,
tranquillity, and light?
It is not easy, I know, to free oneself
wholly from
traditional interpretation, for it often succeeds in reasserting its
sway upon
us at the very moment we strain every nerve to escape from our bondage.
So has
it happened with Ibsen, who, in his search for a new and almost
scientific form
of fatality, erected the veiled, majestic, tyrannical figure of
heredity in the
centre of the very best of his dramas. But it is not the scientific
mystery of
heredity which awakens within us those human fears that lie so much
deeper than
the mere animal fear; for heredity alone could no more achieve this
result than
could the scientific mystery of a dreaded disease, a stellar or marine
phenomenon. No, the fear that differs so essentially from the one
called forth
by an imminent natural danger, is aroused within us by the obscure idea
of
justice which heredity assumes in the drama; by the daring
pronouncement that
the sins of the fathers are almost invariably visited on the children;
by the
suggestion that a sovereign Judge, a goddess of the species, is for
ever watching
our actions, inscribing them on her tablets of bronze, and balancing in
her
eternal hands rewards long deferred and never-ending punishment. In a
word,
even while we deny it, it is the face of God that reappears; and from
beneath
the flagstone one had believed to be sealed for ever comes once again
the
murmur of the very ancient flame of Hell. This new form of fatality, or fatal
justice, is less
defensible, and less acceptable too, than the ancient and elementary
power,
which, being general and undefined, and offering no too strict
explanation of
its actions, lent itself to a far greater number of situations. In the
special
case selected by Ibsen, it is not impossible that some kind of
accidental
justice may be found, as it is not impossible that the arrow a blind
man shoots
into a crowd may chance to strike a parricide. But to found a law upon
this
accidental justice is a fresh perversion of mystery, for elements are
thereby
introduced into human morality which have no right to be there;
elements which
we would welcome, which would be of value, if they stood for definite
truth;
but seeing that they are as alien to truth as to actual life, they
should be
ruthlessly swept aside. I have shown elsewhere that our experience
fails to
detect the most minute trace of justice in the phenomena of heredity,
or in
other words, that it fails to discover the slightest moral connection
between
the cause: the fault of the father, and the effect: the punishment or
reward of
the child. The poet has the right to fashion
hypotheses, and to
forge his way ahead of reality. But it will often happen that, when he
imagines
himself to be far in advance, he will truly have done no more than turn
in a
circle; that where he believes that he has discovered new truth, he has
merely
strayed on to the track of a buried illusion. In the case I have named,
for the
poet to have taught us more than experience teaches, he should have
ventured
still further, perhaps, in the negation of justice. But whatever our
opinion
may be on this point, it at least is clear that the poet who desires
his
hypotheses to be legitimate, and of service, must take heed that they
be not
too manifestly contrary to the experience of everyday life, for in that
case
they become useless and dangerous — scarcely honourable even, if the
error be
deliberately made. And now, what are we to conclude from all
this? Many
things, if one will, but this above all: that it behoves the
“interpreter of
life,” no less than those who are living that life, to exercise
greatest care
in their manner of handling and admitting mystery, and to discard the
belief
that whatever is noblest and best in life or in drama must of necessity
rest in
the part that admits of no explanation. There are many most beautiful,
most
human, most admirable works which are almost entirely free from this
“disquiet
of universal mystery.” We derive no greatness, sublimity, or depth,
from
unceasingly fixing our thoughts on the infinite and the unknown. Such
meditation becomes truly helpful only when it is the unexpected reward
of the
mind that has loyally, unreservedly, given itself to the study of the
finite
and the knowable and to such a mind it will soon be revealed how
strangely
different is the mystery which precedes what one does not know from the
mystery
that follows closely on what one has learned. The first would seem to
contain
many sorrows, but that is only because the sorrows are grouped too
closely, and
have their home upon two or three peaks that stand too nearly together.
In the
second is far less sadness, for its area is vast; and when the horizon
is wide,
there exists no sorrow so great but it takes the form of a hope. [31] Yes, human life, viewed as a whole, may
appear
somewhat sorrowful; and it is easier, in a manner pleasanter even, to
speak of
its sorrows and let the mind dwell on them, than to go in search of,
and bring
into prominence, the consolations life has to offer. Sorrows abound —
infallible, evident sorrows; consolations, or rather the reasons
wherefore we
accept with some gladness the duty of life, are rare and uncertain, and
hard of
detection. Sorrows seem noble, and lofty, and fraught with deep
mystery; with
mystery that almost is personal, that we feel to be near to us.
Consolations
appear egotistical, squalid, at times almost base. But for all that,
and
whatever their ephemeral likeness may be, we have only to draw closer
to them
to find that they too have their mystery; and if this seem less visible
and
less comprehensible, it is only because it lies deeper and is far more
mysterious. The desire to live, the acceptance of life as it is, may
perhaps be
mere vulgar expressions; but, yet they are probably in unconscious
harmony with
laws that are vaster, more conformable with the spirit of the universe,
and
therefore more sacred, than is the desire to escape the sorrows of
life, or the
lofty but disenchanted wisdom that for ever dwells on those sorrows. [32] Our impulse is always to depict life as
more
sorrowful than truly it is; and this is a serious error, to be excused
only by
the doubts that at present hang over us. No satisfying explanation has
so far
been found. The destiny of man is as subject to unknown forces to-day
as it was
in the days of old; and though it be true that some of these forces
have
vanished, others have arisen in their stead. The number of those that
are
really all-powerful has in no way diminished. Many attempts have been
made, and
in countless fashions, to explain the action of these forces and
account for
their intervention; and one might almost believe that the poets, aware
of the
futility of these explanations in face of a reality which, all things
notwithstanding, is ever revealing more and more of itself, have fallen
back on
fatality as in some measure representing the inexplicable, or at least
the
sadness of the inexplicable. This is all that we find in Ibsen, the
Russian
novels, the highest class of modern fiction, Flaubert, etc. (see War
and Peace,
for instance, L’Education Sentimentale, and many others). It is true that the fatality shown is no
longer the
goddess of old, or rather (at least to the bulk of mankind) the clearly
determinate God, inflexible, implacable, arbitrary, blind, although
constantly
watchful; the fatality of to-day is vaster, more formless, more vague,
less
human or actively personal, more indifferent and more universal. In a
word, it
is now no more than a provisional appellation bestowed, until better be
found,
on the general and inexplicable misery of man. In this sense we may
accept it,
perhaps, though we do no more than give a new name to the unchanging
enigma,
and throw no light on the darkness. But we have no right to exaggerate
its
importance or the part that it plays; no right to believe that we are
truly
surveying mankind and events from a point of some loftiness, beneath a
definitive light, or that there is nothing to seek beyond, because at
times we
become deeply conscious of the obscure and invincible force that lies
at the
end of every existence. Doubtless, from one point of view, unhappiness
must
always remain the portion of man, and the fatal abyss be ever open
before him,
vowed as he is to death, to the fickleness of matter, to old age and
disease.
If we fix our eyes only upon the end of a life, the happiest and most
triumphant existence must of necessity contain its elements of misery
and
fatality. But let us not make a wrong use of these words; above all,
let us
not, through listlessness, or undue inclination to mystic sorrow, be
induced to
lessen the part of what could be explained if we would only give more
eager
attention to the ideas, the passions and feelings of the life of man
and the
nature of things. Let us always remember that we are steeped in the
unknown;
for this thought is the most fruitful of all, the most sustaining and
salutary.
But the neutrality of the unknown does not warrant our attributing to
it a
force, designs, or hostility, which it cannot be proved to possess. At
Erfurt,
in his famous interview with Goethe, Napoleon is said to have spoken
disparagingly of the dramas in which fatality plays a great part, — the
plays
that we, in our “passion for calamity,” are apt to consider the finest.
“They
belong,” he remarked, “to an epoch of darkness; but how can fatality
touch us
to-day? Policy — that is fatality!" Napoleon’s dictum is not very
profound;
policy is only the merest fragment of fatality; and his destiny soon
made it
manifest to him that the desire to contain fatality within the narrow
bounds of
policy was no more than a vain endeavour to imprison in a fragile vase
the
mightiest of the spiritual rivers that bathe our globe. And yet,
incomplete as
this thought of Napoleon’s may have been, it still throws some light on
a
tributary of the great river. It was a little thing, perhaps, but on
these
uncertain shores it is the difference between a little thing and
nothing that
kindles the energy of man and confirms his destiny. By this ray of
light, such
as it was, he long was enabled to dominate all that portion of the
unknown
which he declined to term fatality. To us who come after him, the
portion of
the unknown that he controlled may well seem insufficient, if surveyed
from an
eminence, and yet it was truly one of the vastest that the eye of man
has ever
embraced. Through its means every action of his was
accomplished, for evil or good. This is not the place to judge him, or
even to
wonder whether the happiness of a century might not have been better
served had
he allowed events to guide him: what we are considering here is the
docility of
the unknown. For us, with our humbler destinies, the problem still is
the same,
and the principle too; the principle being that of Goethe: “to stand on
the
outermost limit of the conceivable; but never to overstep this line,
for beyond
it begins at once the land of chimeras, whose phantoms and mists are
fraught
with danger to the mind.” It is only when the intervention of the
mysterious,
irresistible, or invisible becomes strikingly real, actually
perceptible,
intelligent, and moral, that we are entitled to yield, or lay down our
arms,
meekly accepting the inactive silence they bring; but their
intervention,
within these limits, is rarer than one imagines. Let us recognise that
mystery
of this kind exists; but, until it reveal itself, we have not the right
to
halt, or relax our efforts; not the right to cast down our eyes in
submission,
or be silent, and resigned. |