Web
and Book design,
Copyright, Kellscraft Studio 1999-2015 (Return to Web Text-ures) |
Click
Here to return to
Japan: An Attempt at Interpretation Content Page Return to the Previous Chapter |
(HOME)
|
The Higher Buddhism PHILOSOPHICAL
Buddhism requires some brief consideration in this place, — for two reasons.
The first is that misapprehension or ignorance of the subject has rendered
possible the charge of atheism against the intellectual classes of Japan, The
second reason is that some persons imagine the Japanese common people — that is
to say, the greater part of the nation — believers in the doctrine of Nirvâna
as extinction (though, as a matter of fact, even the meaning of the word is unknown
to the masses), and quite resigned to vanish from the face of the earth,
because of that incapacity for struggle which the doctrine is supposed to
create. A little serious thinking ought to convince any intelligent man that no
such creed could ever have been the religion of either a savage or a civilized
people. But myriads of Western minds are ready at all times to accept
statements of impossibility without taking the trouble to think about them; and
if I can show some of my readers how far beyond popular comprehension the
doctrines of the higher Buddhism really are, something will have been
accomplished for the cause of truth and common-sense. And besides the reasons
already given for dwelling upon the subject, there is this third and special reason,
— that it is one of extraordinary interest to the student of modern philosophy. Before
going further, I must remind you that the metaphysics of Buddhism can be
studied anywhere else quite as well as in Japan, since the more important sutras
have been translated into various European languages, and most of the
untranslated texts edited and published. The texts of Japanese Buddhism are
Chinese; and only Chinese scholars are competent to throw light upon the minor
special phases of the subject. Even to read the Chinese Buddhist canon of 7000
volumes is commonly regarded as an impossible feat, — though it has certainly
been accomplished in Japan. Then there are the commentaries, the varied
interpretations of different sects, the multiplications of later doctrine, to
heap confusion upon confusion. The complexities of Japanese Buddhism are
incalculable; and those who try to unravel them soon become, as a general rule,
hopelessly lost in the maze of detail. All this has nothing to do with my
present purpose. I shall have very little to say about Japanese Buddhism as
distinguished from other Buddhism, and nothing at all to say about
sect-differences. I shall keep to general facts as regards the higher doctrine,
— selecting from among such facts only those most suitable for the illustration
of that doctrine. And I shall not take up the subject of Nirvâna, in spite of
its great importance, — having treated it as fully as I was able in my Gleanings in Buddha-Fields, — but confine
myself to the topic of certain analogies between the conclusions of Buddhist
metaphysics and the conclusions of contemporary Western thought. In the
best single volume yet produced in English on the subject of Buddhism,1
the late Mr. Henry Clarke Warren observed: "A large part of the pleasure
that I have experienced in the study of Buddhism has arisen from what I may
call the strangeness of the intellectual landscape. All the ideas, the modes of
argument, even the postulates assumed and not argued about, have always seemed so
strange, so different from anything to which I have been accustomed, that I
felt all the time as though walking in Fairyland. Much of the charm that the
Oriental thoughts and ideas have for me appears to be because they so seldom
fit into Western categories."... The serious attraction of Buddhist
philosophy could not be better suggested: it is indeed “the strangeness of the
intellectual Landscape,” as of a world inside-out and upside-down, that has
chiefly interested Western thinkers heretofore. Yet after all, there is a class
of Buddhist concepts which can be fitted, or very nearly fitted, into Western
categories. The higher Buddhism is a kind of Monism; and it includes doctrines
that accord, in the most surprising manner, with the scientific theories of the
German and the English monists. To my thinking, the most curious part of the
subject, and its main interest, is represented just by these accordances,
particularly in view of the fact that the Buddhist conclusions have been
reached through mental processes unknown to Western thinking, and unaided by
any knowledge of science.... I venture to call myself a student of Herbert
Spencer; and it was because of my acquaintance with the Synthetic Philosophy that
I came to find in Buddhist philosophy a more than romantic interest. For
Buddhism is also a theory of evolution, though the great central idea of our
scientific evolution (the law of progress from homogeneity to heterogeneity) is
not correspondingly implied by Buddhist doctrine as regards the life of this
world. The course of evolution as we conceive it, according to Professor
Huxley, “must describe a trajectory like that of a ball fired from a mortar; and
the sinking half of that course is as much a part of the general process of
evolution as the rising.” The highest point of the trajectory would represent what
Mr. Spencer calls Equilibration, — the supreme point of development preceding
the period of decline; but, in Buddhist evolution, this supreme point vanishes
into Nirvâna. I can best illustrate the Buddhist position by asking you to
imagine the trajectory line upside-down, — a course descending out of the
infinite, touching ground, and ascending again to mystery... Nevertheless, some
Buddhist ideas do offer the most startling analogy with the evolutional ideas
of our own time; and even those Buddhist concepts most remote from Western thought
can be best interpreted by the help of illustrations and of language borrowed
from modern science. I think
that we may consider the most remarkable teachings of the higher Buddhism,
excluding the doctrine of Nirvâna, for the reason already given, — to be the
following: — That there is but one Reality; That the consciousness is not the real Self; — That Matter is an aggregate of phenomena created by
the force of acts and thoughts; — That all objective and subjective existence is made
by Karma, — the present being the creation of the past, and the actions of the
present and the past, in combination, determining the conditions of the
future.... (Or, in other words, that
the universe of Matter, and the universe of [conditioned] Mind, represent in
their evolution a strictly moral order.) It will
be worth while now to briefly consider these doctrines in their relation to
modern thought, beginning with the first, which is Monism: — All
things having form or name, — Buddhas, gods, men, and all living creatures, — suns,
worlds, moons, the whole visible cosmos, — are transitory phenomena....
Assuming, with Herbert Spencer, that the test of reality is permanence, one can
scarcely question this position; it differs little from the statement with
which the closing chapter of the First
Principles concludes: — "Though
the relation of subject and object renders necessary to us those antithetical
conceptions of Spirit and Matter, the one is no less than the other to be
regarded as but a sign of the Unknown Reality which underlies both." — Edition of 1894. For
Buddhism the sole reality is the Absolute, — Buddha as unconditioned and
Infinite Being. There is no other veritable existence, whether of Matter or of
Mind; there is no real individuality or personality; the "I” and the
"Not-I" are essentially nowise different. We are reminded of Mr.
Spencer's position, that "it is one and the same Reality which is
manifested to us both subjectively and objectively." Mr. Spencer, goes on
to say: "Subject and Object, as actually existing, can never be contained
in the consciousness produced by the cooperation
of the two, though they are necessarily implied by it; and the antithesis
of Subject and Object, never to be transcended while consciousness lasts,
renders impossible all knowledge of that Ultimate Reality in which Subject and
Object are united.".... I do not think that a master of the higher
Buddhism would dispute Mr. Spencer's doctrine of Transfigured Realism. Buddhism
does not deny the actuality of phenomena as phenomena, but denies their
permanence, and the truth of the appearances which they present to our
imperfect senses. Being transitory, and not what they seem, they are to be
considered in the nature of illusions, — impermanent manifestations of the only
permanent Reality. But the Buddhist position is not agnosticism: it is
astonishingly different, as we shall presently see. Mr. Spencer states that we
cannot know the Reality so long as consciousness lasts, — because while
consciousness lasts we cannot transcend the antithesis of Object and Subject,
and it is this very antithesis which makes consciousness possible. "Very
true," the Buddhist metaphysician would reply; “we cannot know the sole
Reality while consciousness lasts. But
destroy consciousness, and the Reality becomes cognizable. Annihilate the
illusion of Mind, and the light will come." This destruction of
consciousness signifies Nirvâna, — the extinction of all that we call Self.
Self is blindness: destroy it, and the Reality will be revealed as infinite
vision and infinite peace. We have
now to ask what, according to Buddhist philosophy, is the meaning of the
visible universe as phenomenon, and the nature of the consciousness that
perceives. However transitory, the phenomenon makes an impression upon
consciousness; and consciousness itself, though transitory, has existence; and
its perceptions, however delusive, are perceptions of actual relation. Buddhism
answers that both the universe and the consciousness are merely aggregates of
Karma — complexities incalculable of conditions shaped by acts and thoughts
through some enormous past. All substance and all conditioned mind (as
distinguished from unconditioned mind) are products of acts and thoughts: by
acts and thoughts the atoms of bodies have been integrated; and the affinities
of those atoms — the polarities of them, as a scientist might say — represent tendencies
shaped in countless vanished lives. I may quote here from a modern Japanese treatise
on the subject: — "The
aggregate actions of all sentient beings give birth to the varieties of
mountains, rivers, countries, etc. They are caused by aggregate actions, and so
are called aggregate fruits. Our present life is the reflection of past
actions. Men consider these reflections as their real selves. Their eyes,
noses, ears, tongues, and bodies — as well as their gardens, woods, farms,
residences, servants, and maids — men imagine to be their own possessions; but,
in fact, they are only results endlessly produced by innumerable actions. In
tracing every thing back to the ultimate limits of the past, we cannot find a
beginning: hence it is said that death and birth have no beginning. Again, when
seeking the ultimate limit of the future, we cannot find the end."2 This
teaching that all things are formed by Karma — whatever is good in the universe
representing the results of meritorious acts or thoughts; and what ever is
evil, the results of evil acts or thoughts — has the approval of five of the
great sects; and we may accept it as a leading doctrine of Japanese Buddhism....
The cosmos is, then, an aggregate of Karma; and the mind of man is an aggregate
of Karma; and the beginnings thereof are unknown, and the end cannot be
imagined. There is a spiritual evolution, of which the goal is Nirvâna; but we
have no declaration as to a final state of universal rest, when the shaping of
substance and of mind will have ceased forever.... Now the Synthetic Philosophy
assumes a very similar position as regards the evolution of phenomena: there is
no beginning to evolution, nor any conceivable end. I quote from Mr. Spencer's
reply to a critic in the North American
Review; — "That
‘absolute commencement of organic life upon the globe,’ which the reviewer says
I 'cannot evade the admission of,' I distinctly deny. The affirmation of universal
evolution is in itself the negation of an absolute commencement of anything.
Construed in terms of evolution, every kind of being is conceived as a product
of modification wrought by insensible gradations upon a preexisting kind of
being; and this holds as fully of the supposed ‘commencement of organic life’ as
of all subsequent developments of organic life.... That organic matter was not
produced all at once, but was reached through steps, we are well warranted in
believing by the experiences of chemists."3... Of course
it should be understood that the Buddhist silence, as to a beginning and an
end, concerns only the production of phenomena, not any particular existence of
groups of phenomena. That of which no beginning or end can be predicated is
simply the Eternal Becoming. And, like the older Indian philosophy from which
it sprang, Buddhism teaches the alternate apparition and disparition of
universes. At certain prodigious periods of time, the whole cosmos of "one
hundred thousand times ten millions of worlds" vanishes away, — consumed
by fire or otherwise destroyed, — but only to be reformed again. These periods
are called " World-Cycles," and each World-Cycle is divided into four
"Immensities," but we need not here consider the details of the
doctrine. It is only the fundamental idea of a evolutional rhythm that is
really interesting. I need scarcely remind the reader that the alternate
disintegration and reintegration of the cosmos is also a scientific conception,
and a commonly accepted article of evolutional belief. I may quote, however,
for other reasons, the paragraph expressing Herbert Spencer's views upon the
subject: — "Apparently
the universally coexistent forces of attraction and repulsion, which, as we
have seen, necessitate rhythm in all minor changes throughout the Universe,
also necessitate rhythm in the totality of changes, — produce now an
immeasurable period during which the attractive forces, predominating, cause
universal concentration; and then an immeasurable period during which the
repulsive forces, predominating, cause diffusion, — alternate eras of Evolution
and Dissolution. And thus there is suggested to us the conception of a past
during which there have been successive Evolutions analogous to that which is
now going on; and a future during which successive other such Evolutions may go
on — ever the same in principle, but never the same in concrete result." —
First Principles, § 183.4 Further
on, Mr. Spencer has pointed out the vast logical consequence involved by this
hypothesis: — "If,
as we saw reason to think, there is an alternation of Evolution and Dissolution
in the totality of things, — if, as we are obliged to infer from the
Persistence of Force, the arrival at either limit of this vast rhythm brings
about the conditions under which a counter-movement commences, — if we are
hence compelled to entertain the conception of Evolutions that have filled an
immeasurable past, and Evolutions that will fill an immeasurable future, we can
no longer contemplate the visible creation as having a definite beginning or
end, or as being isolated. It becomes unified with all existence before and
after; and the Force which the Universe presents falls into the same category
with its Space and Time as admitting of no limitation in thought."5
— First Principles, § 190. The
foregoing Buddhist positions sufficiently imply that the human consciousness is
but a temporary aggregate, — not an eternal entity. There is no permanent self:
there is but one eternal principle in all life, — the supreme Buddha. Modern Japanese
call this Absolute the "Essence of Mind." "The fire fed by
faggots,” writes one of these, "dies when the faggots have been consumed;
but the essence of fire is never destroyed.... All things in the Universe are
Mind." So stated, the position is unscientific; but as for the conclusion
reached, we may remember that Mr. Wallace has stated almost exactly the same
thing, and that there are not a few modern preachers of the doctrine of a
"universe of mind-stuff." The hypothesis is "unthinkable."
But the most serious thinker will agree with the Buddhist assertion that the
relation of all phenomena to the unknowable is merely that of waves to sea. “Every
feeling and thought being but transitory," says Mr. Spencer, "an
entire life made up of such feelings and thoughts being but transitory, — nay,
the objects amid which life is passed, though less transitory, being severally
in course of losing their individualities quickly or slowly, — we learn that
the one thing permanent is the Unknown Reality hidden under all these changing
shapes," Here the English and the Buddhist philosophers are in accord; but
thereafter they suddenly part company. For Buddhism is not agnosticism, but
gnosticism, and professes to know the unknowable. The thinker of Mr. Spencer's
school cannot make assumptions as to the nature of the sole Reality, nor as to
the reason of its manifestations. He must confess himself intellectually incapable
of comprehending the nature of force, matter, or motion. He feels justified in accepting
the hypothesis that all known elements have been evolved from one primordial
undifferentiated substance, — the chemical evidence for this hypothesis being
very strong. But he certainly would not call that primordial substance a
substance of mind, nor attempt to explain the character of the forces that
effected its integration. Again, though Mr. Spencer would probably acknowledge
that we know of matter only as an aggregate of forces, and of atoms only as
force-centres, or knots of force, he would not declare that an atom is a force-centre, and nothing else....
But we find evolutionists of the German school taking a position very similar to
the Buddhist position, — which implies a universal sentiency, or, more strictly
speaking, a universal potential-sentiency. Haeckel and other German monists
assume such a condition for all substance. They are not agnostics, therefore,
but gnostics; and their gnosticism very much resembles that of the higher
Buddhism. According
to Buddhism there is no reality save Buddha: all things else are but Karma.
There is but one Life, one Self: human individuality and personality are but
phenomenal conditions of that Self. Matter is Karma; Mind is Karma — that is to
say, mind as we know it: Karma, as visibility, represents to us mass and
quality; Karma, as mentality, signifies character and tendency. The primordial substance
— corresponding to the "protyle" of our Monists — is composed of Five
Elements, which are mystically identified with Five Buddhas, all of whom are
really but different modes of the One. With this idea of a primordial substance
there is necessarily associated the idea of a universal sentiency. Matter is
alive. Now to
the German monists also matter is alive. On the phenomena of cell-physiology,
Haeckel claims to base his conviction that "even the atom is not without
rudimentary form of sensation and will, — or, as it is better expressed, of
feeling (aesthesis), and of
inclination (tropesis), that is to say,
a universal soul of the simplest kind." I may quote also from Haeckel’s Riddle of the Universe the following
paragraph expressing the monistic notion of substance as held by Vogt and others:
— "The
two fundamental forms of substance, ponderable matter and ether, are not dead
and only moved by extrinsic force; but they are endowed with sensation and will
(though, naturally, of the lowest grade); they experience an inclination for
condensation, a dislike of strain; they strive after the one, and struggle
against the other." Less like
a revival of the dreams of the Alchemists is the very probable hypothesis of
Schneider, that sentiency begins with the formation of certain combinations, — that
feeling is evolved from the non-feeling just as organic being has been evolved from
inorganic substance. But all these monist ideas enter into surprising
combination with the Buddhist teaching about matter as integrated Karma; and
for that reason they are well worth citing in this relation. To Buddhist
conception all matter is sentient, — the sentiency varying according to
condition: "even rocks and stones," a Japanese Buddhist text
declares, “can worship Buddha." In the German monism of Professor Haeckel’s
school, the particular qualities and affinities of the atom represent feeling
and inclination, “a soul of the simplest kind"; in Buddhism these
qualities are made by Karma, — that is to say, they represent tendencies formed
in previous states of existence. The hypotheses appear to be very similar. But
there is one immense, all-important difference, between the Occidental and the
Oriental monism. The former would attribute the qualities of the atom merely to
a sort of heredity, — to the persistency of tendencies developed under
chance-influences operating throughout an incalculable past. The latter
declares the history of the atom to be purely moral! All matter, according to
Buddhism, represents aggregated sentiency, making, by its inherent tendencies,
toward conditions of pain or pleasure, evil or good. "Pure actions," writes
the author of Outlines of the Mahâyâna Philosophy,
"bring forth the Pure Lands of all the quarters of the universe; while
impure deeds produce the Impure Lands." That is to say, the matter
integrated by the force of moral acts goes to the making of blissful worlds;
and the matter formed by the force of immoral acts goes to the making of
miserable worlds. All substance, like all mind, has its Karma; planets, like
men, are shaped by the creative power of acts and thoughts; and every atom goes
to its appointed place, sooner or later, according to the moral or immoral
quality of the tendencies that inform it. Your good or bad thought or deed will
not only affect your next rebirth, but will likewise affect in some sort the
nature of worlds yet unevolved, wherein, after innumerable cycles, you may have
to live again. Of course, this tremendous idea has no counterpart in modern
evolutional philosophy. Mr, Spencer's position is well known; but I must quote
him for the purpose of emphasizing the contrast between Buddhist and scientific
thought: — “...We
have no ethics of nebular condensation, or of sidereal movement, or of
planetary evolution; the conception is not relevant to inorganic matter. Nor,
when we turn to organized things, do we find that it has any relation to the phenomena
of plant-life; though we ascribe to plants superiorities and inferiorities,
leading to successes and failures in the struggle for existence, we do not
associate with them praise or blame. It is only with the rise of sentiency in
the animal world that the subject-matter of ethics originates." — Principles of Ethics, Vol. II, § 326. On the
contrary, it will be seen, Buddhism actually teaches what we may call, to
borrow Mr, Spencer's phrase, “the ethics of nebular condensation," — though
to Buddhist astronomy, the scientific meaning of the term "nebular
condensation" was never known. Of course the hypothesis is beyond the
power of human intelligence to prove or to disprove. But it is interesting, for
it proclaims a purely moral order of the cosmos, and attaches almost infinite
consequence to the least of human acts. Had the old Buddhist metaphysicians
been acquainted with the facts of modern chemistry, they might have applied
their doctrine, with appalling success, to the interpretation of those facts.
They might have explained the dance of atoms, the affinities of molecules, the
vibrations of ether, in the most fascinating and terrifying way by their theory
of Karma.... Here is a universe of suggestion, — most weird suggestion — for
anybody able and willing to dare the experiment of making a new religion, or at
least a new and tremendous system of Alchemy, based upon the notion of a moral
order in the inorganic world! But the
metaphysics of Karma in the higher Buddhism include much that is harder to
understand than any alchemical hypothesis of atom-combinations. As taught by
popular Buddhism, the doctrine of rebirth is simple enough, — signifying no
more than transmigration: you have lived millions of times in the past, and you
are likely to live again millions of times in the future, all the conditions of
each rebirth depending upon past conduct. The common notion is that after a
certain period of bodiless sojourn in this world, the spirit is guided somehow
to the place of its next incarnation. The people, of course, believe in souls.
But there is nothing of all this in the higher doctrine, which denies
transmigration, denies the existence of the soul, denies personality. There is
no Self to be reborn; there is no transmigration — and yet there is rebirth!
There is no real “I" that suffers or is glad — and yet there is new
suffering to be borne or new happiness to be gained! What we call the Self, — the
personal consciousness, — dissolves at the death of the body; but the Karma,
formed during life, then brings about the integration of a new body and a new
consciousness. You suffer in this existence because of acts done in a previous existence
— yet the author of those acts was not identical with your present self! Are
you, then, responsible for the faults of another person? The
Buddhist metaphysician would answer thus: "The form of your question is
wrong, because it assumes the existence of personality, and there is no
personality. There is really no such individual as the ‘you' of the inquiry.
The suffering is indeed the result of errors committed in some anterior
existence or existences; but there is no responsibility for the acts of another
person, since there is no personality. The ‘I' that was and the ‘I' that is
represent in the chain of transitory being aggregations momentarily created by
acts and thoughts; and the pain belongs to the aggregates as condition
resulting from quality." All this sounds extremely obscure: to understand
the real theory we must put away the notion of personality, which is a very
difficult thing to do. Successive births do not mean transmigration in the
common sense of that word, but only the self-propagation of Karma: the
perpetual multiplying of certain conditions by a kind of ghostly gemmation, — if
I may borrow a biological term. The Buddhist illustration, however, is that of
flame communicated from one lamp-wick to another: a hundred lamps may thus be
lighted from one flame, and the hundred flames will all be different, though
the origin of all was the same. Within the hollow flame of each transitory life
is enclosed a part of the only Reality; but this is not a soul that
transmigrates. Nothing passes from birth to birth but Karma, — character or condition. One will
naturally ask how can such a doctrine exert any moral influence whatever? If
the future being shaped by my Karma is to be in nowise identical with my
present self, — if the future consciousness evolved by my Karma is to be essentially another consciousness, — how can I
force myself to feel anxious about the sufferings of that unborn person?
"Again your question is wrong," a Buddhist would answer: “to
understand the doctrine you must get rid of the notion of individuality, and
think, not of persons, but of successive states of feeling and consciousness,
each of which buds out of the other, — a chain of existences interdependently
united."... I may attempt another illustration. Every individual, as we
understand the term, is continually changing. All the structures of the body are
constantly undergoing waste and repair; and the body that you have at this hour
is not, as to substance, the same body that you had ten years ago. Physically
you are not the same person: yet you suffer the same pains, and feel the same
pleasures, and find your powers limited by the same conditions. Whatever
disintegrations and reconstructions of tissue have taken place within you, you
have the same physical and mental peculiarities that you had ten years ago.
Doubtless the cells of your brain have been decomposed and recomposed: yet you experience
the same emotions, recall the same memories, and think the same thoughts.
Everywhere the fresh substance has assumed the qualities and tendencies of the
substance replaced. This persistence of condition is like Karma. The
transmission of tendency remains, though the aggregate is changed.... These few
glimpses into the fantastic world of Buddhist metaphysics will suffice, I
trust, to convince any intelligent reader that the higher Buddhism (to which
belongs the much-discussed and little-comprehended doctrine of Nirvâna) could never
have been the religion of millions almost incapable of forming abstract ideas,
the religion of a population even yet in a comparatively early stage of
religious evolution. It was never understood by the people at all, nor is it
ever taught to them to-day. It is a religion of metaphysicians, a religion of
scholars, a religion so difficult to be understood, even by persons of some
philosophical training, that it might well be mistaken for a system of
universal negation. Yet the reader should now be able to perceive that, because
a man disbelieves in a personal God, in an immortal soul, and in any continuation
of personality after death, it does not follow that we are justified in declaring
him an irreligious person, — especially if he happen to be an Oriental. The
Japanese scholar who believes in the moral order of the universe, the ethical responsibility
of the present to all the future, the immeasurable consequence of every thought
and deed, the ultimate disparition of evil, and the power of attainment to
conditions of infinite memory and infinite vision, — cannot be termed either an
atheist or a materialist, except by bigotry and ignorance. Profound as may be
the difference between his religion and our own, in respect of symbols and
modes of thought, the moral conclusions reached in either case are very much
the same. 1 Buddhism in Translations, by Henry Clarke Warren (Cambridge,
Massachusetts, 1896). Published by Harvard University. 2 Outlines of the Mahâyâna
Philosophy, by S. Kuroda. 3 Principles of Biology, Vol. I, p. 482. 4 This paragraph, from the fourth edition) has been, considerably
qualified in the definitive edition of 1900. 5 Condensed and somewhat modified in the definitive edition of 1900; but,
for present purposes of illustration, the text of the fourth edition has been
preferred |